\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 1 21-MAR-12 13:28
THE PATH OF THE CONSTITUTION:
THE ORIGINAL SYSTEM OF REMEDIES,
HOW IT CHANGED, AND HOW
THE COURT RESPONDED
S
INA
K
IAN
*
This Article explores how the path of the common law shaped some of the Supreme
Court’s most important decisions regarding constitutional remedies. The Article
first introduces the original system of common law remedies for constitutional
rights. It then explains how these remedies atrophied, both doctrinally and
pragmatically, and how this posed deep problems for the constitutional rights that
depended on them. The Article selects three cases—Mapp v. Ohio, Monroe v.
Pape, and Bivens v. Six Unknown Named Agentsto demonstrate how concerns
about those remedies shaped constitutional rights. These cases have been debated
many times over, but for all the debate, there has been scarce attention paid to the
problem the Court was addressing: the relationship between the Constitution and
common law remedies and, more specifically, what to do about constitutional rights
that depended on dwindling common law remedies. Indeed, this relationship hardly
receives any attention in classrooms or scholarship today, yet it is at the core of the
judiciary’s role in implementing the Constitution. This descriptive gap has distorted
our normative debate about the relative merits of these cases. The last part of the
Article suggests four potential methodologies for coherently managing the relation-
ship between the Constitution and common law remedies.
I
NTRODUCTION
................................................. 133
R
I. T
HE
O
RIGINAL
S
YSTEM
................................. 138
R
A. Judicial Enforcement of Constitutional Rights in a
Government of Enumerated Powers................. 138
R
B. Original Remedies Applied in the Antebellum Era . . 145
R
II. E
ROSION OF
C
OMMON
L
AW
R
EMEDIES
................. 149
R
A. Officer Immunity ................................... 150
R
B. Pragmatics .......................................... 159
R
C. The Common Law in a New World ................. 161
R
III. R
ETHINKING
C
ORE
D
ECISIONS OF
C
ONSTITUTIONAL
I
MPLEMENTATION
....................................... 162
R
A. The Exclusionary Rule .............................. 163
R
1. The Federal Exclusionary Rule.................. 166
R
2. Incorporating the Federal Exclusionary Rule .... 176
R
* Copyright
2012 by Sina Kian, Law Clerk to the Honorable Thomas B. Griffith,
United States Court of Appeals for the District of Columbia Circuit, 2010–11; J.D., 2010,
Stanford Law School. I owe thanks to Benjamin Alden, Janet Alexander, Brian Barnes,
Joshua Cohen, Anthony Dick, George Fisher, Robert Gordon, John Harrison, Jake Heller,
Pamela Karlan, Orin Kerr, Amalia Kessler, Lawrence Lessig, Steven Menashi, David
Pozen, Dan Schweitzer, Matthew Seligman, and Eugene Volokh.
132
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 2 21-MAR-12 13:28
April 2012] THE PATH OF THE CONSTITUTION 133
B. Federal Causes of Action ........................... 182
R
1. Monroe v. Pape................................. 182
R
2. Bivens v. Six Unknown Named Agents ......... 190
R
IV. T
HE
C
ONSTITUTIONAL
O
PTIONS
......................... 192
R
A. Option 1: The Stoic Constitution .................... 196
R
B. Option 2: Rights Preservation ....................... 199
R
C. Option 3: A Baseline System of Common Law
Remedies ............................................ 201
R
D. Option 4: The Laboratories of Democracy .......... 202
R
C
ONCLUSION
................................................... 204
R
I
NTRODUCTION
On September 24, 1766, colonial customs officials, accompanied
by a sheriff, knocked on the door of merchant Daniel Malcom. After
presumably brief pleasantries, the officials revealed their writ of assis-
tance—a general warrant issued by a customs official. Mr. Malcom
inspected the warrant and allowed the men into his home, but he specif-
ically denied them access to a locked cellar. Believing the warrant did
not confer authority to enter the cellar, Mr. Malcom informed the offi-
cials that they could not lawfully enter and that he would use force
against them if they tried. The officials abided and left, but not for long.
They returned with a specific search warrant, but this time to a locked
home and a crowd numbering between fifty and three hundred people
gathered to protest the intrusion.
1
One scholar called this “the most
famous search in colonial America.”
2
On February 11, 2010, at 8:30 p.m., a fully armed SWAT team in
Missouri gathered in the dark outside the residence of Jonathan
Whitworth. One officer began knocking on the door, yelling “Police!”
and “Search warrant!” When a resident meekly opened the door, a
member of the team shoved it open, allowing the entire team to storm
the residence. They shot and killed one resident dog, and shot and
wounded another. They arrested Mr. Whitworth, who did not resist,
and led him out of his home. The entire episode took place before Mr.
Whitworth’s wife and seven-year-old son. As a result of the search, the
SWAT team discovered “a grinder, a pipe and a small amount of
1
See J
OHN
P
HILIP
R
EID
, I
NA
R
EBELLIOUS
S
PIRIT
10–25 (1979) (describing the
incident).
2
O
TIS
H. S
TEPHENS
& R
ICHARD
A. G
LENN
, U
NREASONABLE
S
EARCHES AND
S
EIZURES
: R
IGHTS AND
L
IBERTIES
U
NDER THE
L
AW
39 (2006).
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 3 21-MAR-12 13:28
134 NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:132
marijuana.”
3
There are approximately 40,000 such incidents every year
in the United States, and none receive very much attention.
4
Much has changed in our constitutional culture, not least of which
is how these two men could vindicate their rights in court. This Article
describes the original system of remedies, how that system changed,
and how those changes affected constitutional rights as we recognize
them today. Originally, the Constitution was to be implemented
through remedies available for violations of common law rights.
5
For
example, if the customs officials had improperly entered Mr.
Malcom’s home, he could have sued the officials for trespass. If the
search were unconstitutional, the officers would have had no defense
for their actions and would have been liable for money damages. In
the antebellum Union, this was a robust remedy. After the Civil War,
however, the availability and effectiveness of the damages remedy
declined. Officers committing the same offense were increasingly able
to invoke immunity against lawsuits and more generally avoid the
prospect of paying damages for such acts.
This trend seriously threatened constitutional rights
6
and impli-
cated a fundamental question that receives little attention today: What
is the relationship between the Constitution and the common law? In
other words, what, if anything, should the judiciary do when the
common law remedies on which constitutional rights had depended
begin to change in ways that threaten those rights? If Mr. Whitworth’s
rights were violated, and if the common law remedy of trespass were
no longer available, would he be out of luck? This Article selects three
particularly important cases—Mapp v. Ohio,
7
Monroe v. Pape,
8
and
Bivens v. Six Unknown Named Agents of Federal Narcotics Bureau
9
as emblematic of how the problem of dwindling common law reme-
dies affected the Court’s jurisprudence. Today, Mr. Whitworth would
3
David Brennan, Family Questions SWAT Drug Search that Led to Dog’s Death,
C
OLUMBIA
D
AILY
T
RIB
., Feb. 23, 2010, at A1. A video of this event is available at http://
www.youtube.com/watch?v=qpfLLtPJvxA (last visited Feb. 8, 2012).
4
R
ADLEY
B
ALKO
, O
VERKILL
: T
HE
R
ISE OF
P
ARAMILITARY
P
OLICE
R
AIDS IN
A
MERICA
1 (2006).
5
This Article generally refers to these as “common law remedies,” but it is worth
clarifying that remedies for common law (and statutory) rights were available at both law
and equity.
6
Contemporary discussion of constitutional remedies often focuses on the many intri-
cacies of modern remedies, treating common law remedies as obsolete curiosities. Cf., e.g.,
M
ICHAEL
L. W
ELLS
& T
HOMAS
A. E
ATON
, C
ONSTITUTIONAL
R
EMEDIES
: A R
EFERENCE
G
UIDE TO THE
U
NITED
S
TATES
C
ONSTITUTION
11–13 (2002) (devoting fewer than two out
of over two hundred pages to an in-depth discussion of common law remedies).
7
367 U.S. 643 (1961).
8
365 U.S. 167 (1961).
9
403 U.S. 388 (1971).
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 4 21-MAR-12 13:28
April 2012] THE PATH OF THE CONSTITUTION 135
likely find his remedies in these cases: exclusion of evidence (if the
evidence was illegally obtained) and money damages (if the officers
violated his constitutional rights without qualified immunity). Of
course, the Court had other options for how to respond to the chal-
lenge of dwindling common law remedies, and the Article will end by
briefly describing the alternatives.
A more detailed outline of the Article’s structure is as follows.
Part I introduces the enumeration principle—the simple idea, implicit
in popular sovereignty and explicit in the Ninth Amendment, that
powers not given to government are held by the people. The enumera-
tion principle defines “unconstitutional” acts as those that govern-
ment does not have the power to authorize. Part I then explains how
this principle historically interacted with the common law to create a
system of remedies for violations of constitutional rights. Throughout
the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, judicial enforcement of con-
stitutional rights took two forms, both of which were dependent on
the enumeration principle. The first is familiar today: Defendants can
assert constitutional rights as defenses against suits, including criminal
prosecutions. The enumeration principle voids unconstitutional laws
(or unconstitutional applications of laws), thereby guaranteeing that
defendants will not be harmed under the alleged authority of such a
law.
This Article focuses primarily on the second form of remedy:
Those who suffered a violation of their rights were able to bring suit,
in common law or equity, against the responsible agent. The enumera-
tion principle was traditionally understood to flatly prohibit legal rec-
ognition of any law seeking to authorize unconstitutional action. As a
result, if that agent did something unconstitutional, he would have no
legally cognizable defense for violating the plaintiff’s rights. This was
the original system of constitutional remedies, robust and undisputed
in the antebellum Union. In this system, the Constitution was inti-
mately reliant on the common law, and, whether a right was asserted
offensively or defensively, that right depended on the enumeration
principle to void any unconstitutional laws that were otherwise
invoked to justify invading it.
Part II describes how the common law and the Constitution went
their separate ways, such that the Constitution’s policies were no
longer in neat accord with the remedies provided by state common
law regimes. In both doctrine and practice, the common law remedies
withered as tools for enforcing constitutional rights. This change
posed deep challenges for constitutional values. It not only constricted
particular constitutional rights but also threatened to dramatically
rework the balance of federal and state power.
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 5 21-MAR-12 13:28
136 NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:132
In light of the history outlined in Part II, Part III reexamines
three of the most controversial Supreme Court decisions regarding the
adjudication of civil liberties—Mapp, Monroe, and Bivens—to
demonstrate how the dynamics of common law remedies most visibly
affected the Court’s dispositions. For example, the exclusionary rule
that was incorporated in Mapp had its origins not in the minds of
clever jurists, as many now assume, but in a simple property law
remedy: If someone took your property, you could sue to get it back.
But the waning adequacy of common law remedies increased the sali-
ence and appeal of federal remedies that were free from the whims of
state common law—thereby giving rise to cases like Monroe and
Bivens. Generally speaking, the logic of these cases—today often
characterized as necessary or implied by some, and overreaching or
made-up law by others—is actually intimately reliant on the nature
and path of common law remedies. Thus, the contribution of Part III,
standing alone, is to provide a doctrinal history of these cases that has
heretofore been lacking.
The broader ambition of the Article is to renew the vigorous
debate over these cases with this history in mind. The literature’s
failure to describe the motivation behind the outcomes in these cases
has accordingly distorted the normative debate about their place in
our constitutional system. Those who support these decisions tend to
defend them as good policy or perhaps as vaguely implied or inherent
in the Bill of Rights. Opponents dismiss these cases as bad policy or
unsupported by originalist principles.
Yet this debate dramatically misrepresents the cases and the chal-
lenges they posed to the jurists who considered them. The existing
literature is at best unable to describe why these cases came out the
way they did and at worst simply misguided. The primary mistake is
that the scholarship draws a narrative of constitutional rights without
considering the role of remedies. This is surprising because the idea
that any meaningful discussion of rights ought to consider remedies is
not just a central tenet of so-called “legal realism”
10
but an intuition
10
See, e.g., Oliver Wendell Holmes, The Path of the Law, 10 H
ARV
. L. R
EV
. 457, 458
(1897) (“[A] legal duty so called is nothing but a prediction that if a man does or omits
certain things he will be made to suffer in this or that way by judgment of the court;—and
so of a legal right.”).
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 6 21-MAR-12 13:28
April 2012] THE PATH OF THE CONSTITUTION 137
that runs deep in Anglo-American legal thought,
11
and one that
retains influence today.
12
Finally, Part IV seeks to introduce a more useful methodological
debate, that is, the “options” for judicial enforcement of constitutional
rights. The options in Part IV provide distinct alternatives for how to
deal with the problem of the dwindling common law remedies that
once serviced constitutional rights. The first option is to accept a net
loss in judicially enforced constitutional protections. That is, constitu-
tional rights are only enforceable insofar as their antecedent, non-
constitutional remedies allow, and if those remedies dwindle in scope
or availability, and if constitutional rights deflate as a result, then so
be it—that is a problem for the political system, not the federal judi-
ciary. For those unwilling to incur deflation of constitutional rights,
there are essentially three other options. The second is to adapt—to
interpret and recalibrate rights in order to preserve them in the face of
otherwise eroding remedies. The third is to require a baseline of spe-
cific common law remedies and to have the judiciary ensure their
availability. This approach would require a due process right to a
remedial process not inconsistent with those available in 1791 and
1868. The fourth is to leave the entire question of remedies to the
states, thereby accepting a diversity of approaches while monitoring to
ensure that the remedies each state provides are constitutionally
adequate.
While this Article does not address the normative question of
which option is best, it provides these options as a useful and unexam-
ined methodological starting point for how to handle the
Constitution’s relationship with the common law. Doing so challenges
the way scholars think about and debate the underlying cases. As a
descriptive matter, cases like Mapp, Monroe, and Bivens should be
viewed not as blatant, politically- motivated expansions of rights, but
11
See, e.g., Marbury v. Madison, 5 U.S. (1 Cranch) 137, 163 (1803) (“The government
of the United States has been emphatically termed a government of laws, and not of men.
It will certainly cease to deserve this high appellation, if the laws furnish no remedy for the
violation of a vested legal right.”); Ashby v. White, (1703) 92 Eng. Rep. 126 (H.L.) 136; 2
Ld. Raym 938, 954 (Holt, C.J.) (“[I]t is a vain thing to imagine a right without a remedy.”);
1 W
ILLIAM
B
LACKSTONE
, C
OMMENTARIES
55–56 (Univ. of Chicago Press 1979) (1765)
(“For in vain would rights be declared, in vain directed to be observed, if there were no
method of recovering and asserting those rights, when wrongfully withheld or invaded.
This is what we mean properly, when we speak of the protection of the law.”).
12
For a particularly compelling recent example, see Daryl J. Levinson, Rights
Essentialism and Remedial Equilibration, 99 C
OLUM
. L. R
EV
. 857, 857 (1999), in which the
author states that “[n]o less than in contract and property law—where from Holmes to
Calabresi and Melamed we have recognized that rights and remedies are functionally inter-
related—rights and remedies in constitutional law are interdependent and inextricably
intertwined.”
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 7 21-MAR-12 13:28
138 NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:132
rather as decisions based on these options and constraints. As a nor-
mative matter, the debate over constitutional rights often assumes
that a particular constitutional outcome is available or it is not. For
example, scholars speak for and against the exclusionary rule. This is
incomplete. One’s position on the exclusionary rule is, or at least
should be, tied to how one understands the relationship between the
Constitution and the common law—as emblematic of a choice given
the four options. This Article tells the story of how the Court came to
negotiate the contours of that relationship.
I
T
HE
O
RIGINAL
S
YSTEM
The original system of constitutional remedies worked as follows:
If an officer violated one of your constitutional rights, you could sue
him as an individual, and you would win because he would have no
defense for his wrongful act. Behind this simple system, however,
lurks an interesting interplay of institutions and legal doctrines.
Section A will describe how sovereign immunity and the enumeration
principle contributed to making this system the primary means by
which constitutional rights were offensively asserted (and thus how
remedies for violations of these rights were provided). Section B will
then discuss major antebellum cases that demonstrate these principles
at work.
A. Judicial Enforcement of Constitutional Rights
in a Government of Enumerated Powers
The original system of judicial remedies for constitutional trans-
gressions arose from the interplay of two doctrines. First, the principle
of sovereign immunity prohibited individuals from suing the govern-
ment, state or federal, without first obtaining the government’s con-
sent.
13
The act of expelling the Crown, embodied in the Declaration of
Independence, made clear that that immunity was not boundless, but
this left ambiguity as to whether milder forms of the doctrine survived
the Revolution. This became the first issue docketed before the brand
new Supreme Court of the United States in Van Staphorst v.
Maryland,
14
where the Governor of Maryland was issued a summons
for a debt owed to Van Staphorst. But before the case could be
13
See generally Caleb Nelson, Sovereign Immunity as a Doctrine of Personal
Jurisdiction, 115 H
ARV
. L. R
EV
. 1559 (2002) (discussing the Founding-era understanding of
sovereign immunity as denying individuals the ability to command states to appear in
court).
14
M
ARCUS
M
AEVA
, 5 T
HE
D
OCUMENTARY
H
ISTORY OF THE
S
UPREME
C
OURT OF THE
U
NITED
S
TATES
, 1789–1800, at 7 (1994) (“The question of the suability of states surfaced in
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 8 21-MAR-12 13:28
April 2012] THE PATH OF THE CONSTITUTION 139
decided, Maryland settled in order to avoid giving the Federalist
Supreme Court an opportunity to set a precedent threatening its
sovereignty.
15
The issue did not evade review for long. Two years later, in 1793,
the Court handed down its controversial opinion in Chisholm v.
Georgia,
16
holding that states were indeed amenable to suit. In
response, the states rallied and passed the Eleventh Amendment, clar-
ifying that the provision of Article III interpreted by Chisholm did not
usurp long standing assumptions about immunity as inherent to sover-
eignty.
17
The logic of sovereign immunity also required that the doc-
trine of respondeat superior have no application in suits against
government officials, meaning that unconsenting states could not be
held liable for the conduct of their officers.
18
Government officers
who personally committed any wrong, in tort or otherwise, were liable
only as individuals, even if that tort was committed within the scope of
their employment.
The second relevant doctrine goes to the core of the Constitution
and American political philosophy: the enumeration principle. The
rest of this Section will briefly discuss the role of that principle in the
debate over the Bill of Rights, and the implications of that debate—
more precisely its premises—for how the judiciary was drafted to
enforce the Constitution.
The idea of enumerated powers—that powers not explicitly con-
ferred are withheld—formed the core of Alexander Hamilton’s argu-
ment against a bill of rights, “[f]or why declare that things shall not be
done which there is no power to do?”
19
This question contained a syl-
logism premised on the American Revolution’s most important con-
tribution to the organization of government: popular sovereignty.
20
the very first case entered on the Supreme Court docket, Van Staphorst v. Maryland, which
commenced in February 1791 and was settled the following year.”).
15
Id. at 19. Maryland’s House of Delegates reported that allowing the case to go on
“may deeply affect the political rights of this state, as an independent member of the
union” and that a “compromise” was preferable to permitting a “precedent to be estab-
lished, by which any individual foreigner may endanger the political and private rights of
this state and her citizens.” Id. (quoting V
OTES AND
P
ROCEEDINGS OF THE
S
TATE OF
M
D
.
H.D., R
EPORT OF THE
C
OMM
.
ON
P
UB
. R
EVENUES
, D
EBTS
,
AND
E
XPENDITURES
, 1st Sess.,
at 89. (Dec. 13, 1791)).
16
2 U.S. (2 Dall.) 419 (1793).
17
See Nelson, supra note 13, at 1585–92 (discussing an interpretation of the language
of Article III in which unconsenting states would not be amenable to suit).
18
J
OSEPH
S
TORY
, C
OMMENTARIES ON THE
L
AW O F
A
GENCY
§ 319 (Boston, Little,
Brown & Co. eds., 6th ed. 1863).
19
T
HE
F
EDERALIST
N
O
. 84, at 537 (Alexander Hamilton) (Henry Cabot Lodge ed.,
New York and London, G.P. Putnam’s Sons 1888).
20
No other nation had realized popular sovereignty so explicitly and so prominently in
practice. As Blackstone put it, “[t]he sovereignty, though always potentially existing in the
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 9 21-MAR-12 13:28
140 NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:132
Legitimacy derives from the people. This means the government has
no more power than what is conferred to it by the people. In such a
system, a constitutionally recognized right can be understood as a
power withheld from the government or an exception to an otherwise
granted power. To Hamilton and like-minded Federalists, enumer-
ating a right where the federal government had no power was
arguably worse than superfluous for two reasons. First, it would imply
a power to regulate the realm protected by that right.
21
Second, the
common law had demonstrated that natural rights reveal themselves
in endless, fact-specific iterations; an exhaustive list being impossible
to create, those rights not listed would be implicitly excluded.
22
The logic was clean; the application, not. Anti-federalists were
quick to respond and, indeed, Hamilton’s argument proved too much:
We find they have, in the ninth section of the first article declared,
that the writ of habeas corpus shall not be suspended, unless in
cases of rebellion,—that no bill of attainder, or ex post facto law,
shall be passed,—that no title of nobility shall be granted by the
United States, etc. . . . Does this Constitution any where grant the
power of suspending the habeas corpus, to make ex post facto laws,
pass bills of attainder, or grant titles of nobility? It certainly does
not in express terms. The only answer that can be given is, that
these are implied in the general powers granted. With equal truth it
may be said, that all the powers which the bills of rights guard
against the abuse of, are contained or implied in the general ones
granted by this Constitution.
23
This debate was animated by a core tradeoff: The need for specific,
enumerated rights becomes more imperative as government is granted
more and broader powers. As some saw it, the powers conferred to
the federal government were broad and vague. The power to do eve-
rything “necessary and proper” in regulating “commerce . . . among
the several States”
24
did not, of its own logic, prevent the federal gov-
ernment from convicting defendants for embargo violations through a
people of every independent nation, or state, is in most of them, usurped by, and con-
founded with, the government. Hence in England it is said to be vested in the parliament:
in France, before the revolution, and still, in Spain, Russia, Turkey and other absolute
monarchies, in the crown, or monarch; in Venice, until the late conquest of that state, in the
doge, and senate, &c.” 1 W
ILLIAM
B
LACKSTONE
, C
OMMENTARIES
app. at 10 (St. George
Tucker ed., William Young Birch & Abraham Small 1803) (1765).
21
See T
HE
F
EDERALIST
, supra note 19, at 537 (“[T]he provision against restraining the
liberty of the press afforded a clear implication, that a power to prescribe proper regula-
tions concerning it was intended to be vested in the national government.”).
22
Id.
23
T
HE
A
NTIFEDERALIST
N
O
. 84, at 245–46 (Morton Borden ed., Mich. State Univ.
Press 1965) (emphasis omitted).
24
U.S. C
ONST
. art. I, § 8, cl. 18.
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 10 21-MAR-12 13:28
April 2012] THE PATH OF THE CONSTITUTION 141
trial by affidavit or in a trial without jury. As Blackstone observed, the
advantage of a written constitution was that it did not leave power
undefined.
25
However, as Hamilton’s reasoning demonstrated, there
was something of a seesaw dynamic between power and rights: The
possibilities were to enumerate broad powers and specific rights, or to
secure broad rights by circumscribing the government’s powers. The
broader the powers conferred to the federal government, the more
salient the need for a bill of rights.
26
By contrast, if the federal govern-
ment were given only narrow and well-defined powers, as it was in the
Articles of Confederation, the need for specific rights seemed less
pressing. Not surprisingly, then, the Articles of Confederation, while
focused on limiting the powers of federal government, did not pay
much attention to individual rights. By contrast, state constitutions,
which conferred broad powers to branches of state government, all
contained bills of rights.
27
This tradeoff was critical. In fact, Madison confided that his sup-
port for a bill of rights was based on the understanding that a demand
for specifically enumerated rights was in lieu of, or at least staved off,
the demand for a more circumscribed federal government.
28
25
According to Blackstone:
The advantages of a written constitution, considered as the original contract of
society must immediately strike every reflecting mind; power, when undefined,
soon becomes unlimited; and the disquisition of social rights where there is no
text to resort to, for their explanation, is a task, equally above ordinary capaci-
ties, and incompatible with the ordinary pursuits, of the body of the people.
But, as it is necessary to the preservation of a free government, established
upon the principles of a representative democracy, that every man should
know his own rights, it is also indispensably necessary that he should be able,
on all occasions, to refer to them.
B
LACKSTONE
, supra note 20, at 154–55; see also id. at 287 (arguing that notwithstanding
Tenth Amendment and Federalist assurances otherwise, the Necessary and Proper Clause
immediately “destroy[ed] the effect of the particular enumeration of powers” and citing
“the act for establishing a bank; the act authorising the president to appoint officers to
volunteer corps of militia; the act declaring that a paper not stamped agreeably thereto,
shall not be admitted as evidence in a state court; the alien and sedition laws, &c”).
26
As Thomas Jefferson put it: “Half a loaf is better than no bread. If we cannot secure
all our rights, let us secure what we can.” Letter from Thomas Jefferson to James Madison
(Mar. 15, 1789), in 14 T
HE
P
APERS OF
T
HOMAS
J
EFFERSON
660 (Julian P. Boyd ed.,
Princeton Univ. Press 1958).
27
See, e.g., F
RANCIS
N
EWTON
T
HORPE
, T
HE
F
EDERAL AND
S
TATE
C
ONSTITUTIONS
(1906) (compiling state constitutions). In a similar vein, it is perhaps not surprising that the
protections offered by the Bill of Rights became more robust, or were at least more often
triggered, following incorporation and the Court’s expanding interpretation of the
Commerce Clause. These shifts required the Bill of Rights to operate alongside a federal
government with growing legislative authority and state governments with considerable
preexisting legislative authority.
28
In a letter, Madison wrote:
The friends of the Constitution . . . wish the revisal to be carried no farther
than to supply additional guards for liberty . . . and are fixed in opposition to
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 11 21-MAR-12 13:28
142 NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:132
This debate, its premises, and its outcome—enumerating broad
powers and carving comparatively narrow rights—were immediately
relevant to how the Constitution was to be implemented by the
branches of government. Whereas William Shakespeare once wrote,
“it is excellent, [t]o have a giant’s strength; but it is tyrannous, [t]o use
it like a giant,”
29
the Constitution reserved from giants the powers it
did not want them to use.
30
This idea—that powers not granted were
reserved completely—was the enumeration principle, and it can be
seen in how laws are passed and enforced. In broad terms, when
passing a law, both houses of Congress must determine, by majority
vote and in accordance with the strictures of Article I, that Congress
has the authority to pass a particular piece of legislation under Article
I and that the proposed legislation does not violate other provisions of
the Constitution, most notably Article I, Section 9 and the Bill of
Rights. The President must conclude the same, and sign the bill into
law to signify that conclusion. Then, the executive branch must
enforce the law and, to the extent it continues to believe the law is
constitutional, defend the law in courts.
31
From here, the judiciary’s involvement takes one of two forms.
32
First, a court may have to determine whether the law is constitutional.
the risk of another Convention . . . . It is equally certain that there are others
who urge a second Convention with the insidious hope of throwing all things
into Confusion, and of subverting the fabric just established, if not the Union
itself.
Letter from James Madison to Thomas Jefferson (Dec. 8, 1788), in T
HE
P
APERS OF
T
HOMAS
J
EFFERSON
, supra note 26, at 340.
29
W
ILLIAM
S
HAKESPEARE
, M
EASURE FOR
M
EASURE
act 2, sc. 2.
30
This commonly held understanding is inherent in the Constitution’s structure. The
Constitution begins as a grant of power from “We the People” to the government, as
“ordain[ed] and establish[ed]” in the Constitution, U.S. C
ONST
. pmbl., and, after enumer-
ating the powers granted to that government, the Constitution proceeds to a Bill of Rights.
The Ninth Amendment then provides that “[t]he enumeration in the Constitution, of cer-
tain rights, shall not be construed to deny or disparage others retained by the people.” Id.
amend. IX. The Tenth Amendment provides that “powers not delegated to the United
States by the Constitution, nor prohibited by it to the States, are reserved to the States
respectively, or to the people.” Id. amend X.
31
This responsibility found recent example in President Obama’s announcement that
he will no longer defend the constitutionality of the Defense of Marriage Act in court.
Press Release, Dep’t of Justice, Statement of the Att’y Gen. on Litig. Involving the Def. of
Marriage Act (Feb. 23, 2011), available at
http://www.justice.gov/opa/pr/2011/February/11-ag-222.html.
32
These two approaches are often described using the sword-shield metaphor. See gen-
erally Walter E. Dellinger, Of Rights and Remedies: The Constitution as a Sword, 85 H
ARV
.
L. R
EV
. 1532 (1972) (describing the alternate uses of constitutional guarantees as “shields”
against government action, and as “swords” in affirmative causes of action against the gov-
ernment). As we will see in the Section about the exclusionary rule, this metaphor, while
useful, should not overstate the degree of distinction between a constitutional right
enforced offensively and one enforced defensively.
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 12 21-MAR-12 13:28
April 2012] THE PATH OF THE CONSTITUTION 143
To the extent that “enforcement” implies a prosecution or a lawsuit
against a party, the defendant can defend himself by challenging the
constitutional validity of the law, thus triggering judicial review.
33
The
court would then have to find, again, that Congress had authority to
pass the law, and that the law, as applied by the executive, did not
violate the defendant’s constitutional rights.
34
This form of judicial
review, affirmed by Marbury v. Madison,
35
has hardly been ques-
tioned since, and generally remains robust today.
36
Second, a court
may be asked to remedy a constitutional wrong. To the extent that
executive “enforcement” of a law constitutes harassment, assault, or
33
For the most recent example, see Bond v. United States, 131 S. Ct. 2355, 2359 (2011),
in which the Court concludes that “a person indicted for violating a federal statute has
standing to challenge its validity on grounds that, by enacting it, Congress exceeded its
powers under the Constitution, thus intruding upon the sovereignty and authority of the
States.” See also id. at 2368 (Ginsburg, J., concurring) (“In short, a law ‘beyond the power
of Congress,’ for any reason, is ‘no law at all.’ The validity of Bond’s conviction depends
upon whether the Constitution permits Congress to enact § 229. Her claim that it does not
must be considered and decided on the merits.” (citing Nigro v. United States, 276 U.S. 332,
341(1928))).
34
Recently this point has been confused in the scholarship. One article, for example,
claims that the First Amendment has no application to the executive branch. See Nicholas
Quinn Rosenkranz, The Subjects of the Constitution, 62 S
TAN
. L. R
EV
. 1209, 1255 (2010).
There, it is claimed that “[a First Amendment] violation has nothing to do with the applica-
tion of the law to any particular person[,]” and that “[t]he violation is complete before the
law is applied at all.” Id. Consequently, the author concludes that
[a] First Amendment freedom-of-speech challenge cannot be an ‘as-applied’ or
‘as-executed’ challenge to executive action; it must be a ‘facial challenge’—that
is, a challenge to legislative action. The alleged constitutional violation must be
visible on the face of the statute: lex ipsa loquitur. And the claimed remedy is a
declaration that the product of the legislative action—the ‘law’—is not law at
all.
Id. This insight is incomplete because it does not fully account for how the result—that the
“law” is “not law at all”—actually does constrain the executive. The First Amendment
restrains the executive by prohibiting Congress from passing laws that would provide exec-
utive officers with valid authority to abridge the freedom of speech. This means that an
executive officer will be liable if he tries to enforce an act of Congress that violates the
First Amendment (because, at risk of being redundant, such an act does not provide valid
authority for the officer’s actions). Because Congress cannot authorize such actions, execu-
tive officers cannot claim such authority.
35
5 U.S. (1 Cranch) 137 (1803).
36
After the court passes on constitutional questions that are properly raised in the
proceeding, the jury implicitly has the opportunity to pass on the constitutionality of a law
or its application through jury nullification. After this, the defendant has at his disposal
direct review, habeas, and the possibility of presidential pardon. And finally, aggrieved
parties may also look to resuscitate incarnations of popular constitutionalism discussed
elsewhere. For example, in the context of an “overly assertive Court,” see generally L
ARRY
D. K
RAMER
, T
HE
P
EOPLE
T
HEMSELVES
: P
OPULAR
C
ONSTITUTIONALISM AND
J
UDICIAL
R
EVIEW
(2004). The author states that “[t]he Constitution leaves room for countless polit-
ical responses . . . Justices can be impeached, the Court’s budget can be slashed, the
President can ignore its mandates, Congress can strip it of jurisdiction or shrink its size or
pack it with new members . . . .” Id. at 249.
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 13 21-MAR-12 13:28
144 NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:132
other wrongs like trespass, the aggrieved individual has historically
been guaranteed due process of law. To secure his life, liberty, and
property, he need look no further than the oldest and most celebrated
method of vindicating natural rights in English history: the common
law. In a suit against an officer “enforcing” a law, the officer would
necessarily invoke his authorization as a defense.
37
The plaintiff would
then have the opportunity to challenge either the officer’s action as
outside the scope of authorization, or the authorization itself as
unconstitutional. If this challenge were successful, the officer would be
defenseless and liable.
38
This was not just a formality, but an outcome
dictated by the enumeration principle and by a commitment to pop-
ular sovereignty.
39
The enumeration principle was thus integrated into every step of
constitutional implementation, from legislating in Congress to final
review on habeas. To say that an action is unconstitutional is to say
that it was done without the authority conferred to government by the
people—either because the power was not conferred, or because it
was specifically withheld in the form of a right. An unconstitutional
action is forceless, like a judgment on United States patent law made
by a provincial bankruptcy court in Canada, or like the government of
France passing a law abolishing the death penalty in the United States.
It is important to note that no particular scheme of remedies nec-
essarily follows from the enumeration principle by itself. The system
only works when the enumeration principle is combined with a system
of remedies like the common law. The common law provides the
remedial mechanism, mainly a forum in which to bring suit and assert
one’s right. The enumeration principle worked inside that forum. In
the context of a suit, it allowed the court to inquire into whether the
Constitution permits the officer’s actions and to negate the officer’s
defense if it does not. The force of the enumeration principle seems
37
See, e.g., Sina Kian, Note, Pleading Sovereign Immunity, 61 S
TAN
. L. R
EV
. 1233,
1246–47 (2009) (describing the dynamics of the pleading requirements in the context of
officer suits).
38
Id. at 1247.
39
Again, this is because popular sovereignty means that power emanates from the
people, and, by extension, the enumeration principle means that government can only
invoke the power enumerated to it by the Constitution. The contours of that power are
defined by general grants of authority (for example, the Commerce Clause) and specific
areas where power is withheld in the form of rights reserved for individuals—for example,
the federal government was not granted authority to inflict cruel and unusual punishment.
Thus, if an officer does inflict such punishment, he cannot avoid liability for assault or
battery by asserting his authority as an officer.
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 14 21-MAR-12 13:28
April 2012] THE PATH OF THE CONSTITUTION 145
simple enough—perhaps too simple—but it will be a critical con-
straint discussed later in the Article.
40
B. Original Remedies Applied in the Antebellum Era
The common law remedy found immediate and robust applica-
tion. Although prominent accounts of the application of these reme-
dies begin with the Supreme Court’s decisions in Cohens v. Virginia
41
or Osborn v. Bank of the United States,
42
the practice had a signifi-
cantly deeper and richer role in the Republic’s history.
43
One of the most noted examples in British common law involved
a trespass action against the King’s Chief Messenger, Nathan
Carrington, who “with force and arms” broke into the home of John
Entick, an associate of the English radical John Wilkes.
44
Carrington
did this under the supposed authority of a warrant from Secretary of
State Lord Halifax, which instructed him “to make strict and diligent
search for . . . the author, or one concerned in the writing of several
weekly very seditious papers.”
45
Entick sued Carrington and the
40
This simple idea also sheds light on other separation of powers questions, or at least
clarifies what precisely is at issue. For example, scholars have long debated whether courts
can issue advisory opinions. See R
ICHARD
H. F
ALLON
, J
R
.
ET AL
., H
ART AND
W
ECHSLER
S
T
HE
F
EDERAL
C
OURTS AND
T
HE
F
EDERAL
S
YSTEM
79–85 (5th ed. 2003) (discussing
various issues associated with advisory opinions). The enumeration principle reorients this
inquiry. If the Constitution “prohibits” advisory opinions, this simply means such opinions
will have no legal effect; they are void. The question is not whether courts can issue advi-
sory opinions, but what effect is given to these opinions. Thus, according to the enumera-
tion principle, courts can issue all the advisory opinions they like, but these opinions have
no legal effect but the power of their reason, like an op-ed or a law review article (this
analysis, of course, does not address the ethics or appropriateness of a judge using the
imprimatur of her office to issue legal opinions that, in effect, amount to little more than an
op-ed). This idea also sheds light on what should be easy cases of wrongly-invoked immu-
nity. For example, there is some evidence that lawmakers believe their legislative immunity
extends to private wrongs against other individuals, thus authorizing lawmakers to drink
and drive, or physically assault others. See, e.g., Marc Lacey, A Legal Privilege that Some
Lawmakers See Broadly, N.Y. T
IMES
, Mar. 11, 2011, at A13 (recounting such instances of
claimed immunities). The enumeration principle, of course, embodies the commonsense
intuition that such invocations of immunity cannot stand, and it does so by asking a simple
question: Was this an authority granted to members of government by the people? As a
general matter, it is safe to say that the license to drink and drive or to freely commit
domestic violence is not the kind of authority granted to representatives by the federal or
state constitutions.
41
19 U.S. (6 Wheat.) 264 (1821).
42
22 U.S. (9 Wheat.) 738 (1824).
43
See, e.g., David E. Engdahl, Immunity and Accountability for Positive Governmental
Wrongs, 44 U. C
OLO
. L. R
EV
. 1, 10 (1972) (noting Cohens as an early Supreme Court case
allowing such a remedy to proceed); Louis L. Jaffe, Suits Against Governments and
Officers: Sovereign Immunity, 77 H
ARV
. L. R
EV
. 1, 21 (1963) (describing Osborn as
“boldly . . . stak[ing]” a wide field for actions against state officers).
44
Entick v. Carrington, (1765) 95 Eng. Rep. 807 (K.B.) 807; 2 Wils. K.B. 275.
45
Id. at 808.
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 15 21-MAR-12 13:28
146 NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:132
officers in trespass and, because the warrant was unconstitutional, he
recovered £1000 against one of the officials who conducted the search,
and £4000 against Lord Halifax
46
—serious sums of money when
accounting for over 200 years of inflation. This case assumed a legen-
dary status in American jurisprudence; the Supreme Court many
years later would refer to it as a “great judgment,” a “landmark[ ] of
English liberty,” a case “welcomed and applauded by the lovers of
liberty in the colonies,” and a “true and ultimate expression of consti-
tutional law.”
47
This practice was not limited to England or post-
independence America; it was a primary legal vehicle by which the
colonies resisted English tyranny.
48
A decade after ratification, the Supreme Court reaffirmed the
legitimacy of judicially enforcing rights in this manner, its harshness
on officers notwithstanding. In Little v. Barreme,
49
the President spe-
cifically instructed the commander of a U.S. warship to intercept and
seize a Danish vessel suspected of violating a nonintercourse law.
However, the President misconstrued the relevant statute, and in fact
there was no legal authority for the seizure.
50
This meant that the
officer’s defense would be void; he had no valid authority to excuse
his actions. The district court ordered restoration of the vessel and its
cargo, but denied damages. The circuit court reversed the denial of
damages, and the Supreme Court upheld the decision of the circuit
court.
51
The officer, for following executive instruction, was ordered
to pay $8504 in damages—approximately $120,000 today. Chief
Justice Marshall paused at the legally correct yet intuitively trouble-
some result. He noted, “I confess the first bias of my mind was very
strong in favor of the opinion that though the instructions of the exec-
utive could not give a right, they might yet excuse from damages,”
52
but he ultimately agreed “that the instructions cannot change the
nature of the transaction, or legalize an act which without those
instructions would have been a plain trespass.”
53
Key here is that
46
See Boyd v. United States, 116 U.S. 616, 626 (1886) (describing the outcome of
Entick v. Carrington).
47
Id.
48
See, e.g.,C
ARL
U
BBELOHDE
, T
HE
V
ICE
-A
DMIRALTY
C
OURTS AND THE
A
MERICAN
R
EVOLUTION
67–68 (1960) (describing customs officer’s seizure of sloop and owner’s sub-
sequent use of common law action to preempt admiralty jurisdiction). This monograph also
explains how colonists hinted or implied that limitations on that common law action were
themselves constitutional infringements, particularly as those limitations applied to the
jury right. See id. at 76–79, 189–90.
49
6 U.S. (2 Cranch) 170 (1804).
50
Id. at 178–79.
51
Id. at 172.
52
Id. at 179.
53
Id.
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 16 21-MAR-12 13:28
April 2012] THE PATH OF THE CONSTITUTION 147
immunizing an officer from damages is a way of authorizing or “legal-
izing” his conduct, and because the enumeration principle prohibits an
unconstitutional act from being “legalized,” it also prohibited immu-
nizing an officer from damages.
Two years later, Chief Justice Marshall addressed the issue again
without pause. In Wise v. Withers, a court martial had imposed fines
on a justice of the peace in the District of Columbia for failing to
enroll for militia duty.
54
Though the statute exempted “the officers,
judicial and executive, of the government of the United States,” the
court martial found that a justice of the peace did not qualify.
55
A
collector entered the defendant’s home and seized property to satisfy
the fine. The Supreme Court disagreed with the court martial’s
reading, held that justices of the peace were exempt from duty,
56
and
found that the collector was personally liable. The Court stated quite
plainly, “it is a principle, that a decision of such a tribunal, in a case
clearly without its jurisdiction, cannot protect the officer who executes
it.”
57
Neither Little nor Wise concerned constitutional rights. Rather,
they affirmed a dynamic that had, at its core, an understanding of gov-
ernmental power. Simply put, government could not exercise power
not delegated to it. At the statutory level, as seen in Little and Wise,
this meant that officers enforcing obligations inconsistent with or in
excess of those imposed by the law were without authority, without
immunity, and subject to suit insofar as their actions violated rights.
It followed, a fortiori, that officers would be subject to suit for
acting beyond the bounds of authority conferred to government by
the Constitution. And so the case law went. The most prominent
example from the Marshall era was Osborn v. Bank of the United
States, where an officer ignored an injunction requiring otherwise and
extracted an unconstitutional tax from the Bank.
58
The state law
“authorizing” the tax was no defense, as states were not empowered
to authorize unconstitutional laws, so the tax collector could be
sued.
59
Likewise, in Davis v. Gray, the plaintiff railroad sued officers
to enjoin them from authorizing settlers to enter the railroad’s land.
The defendants pointed to a law as their authorization, a law the
plaintiffs challenged as violating the Contracts Clause. And because
54
7 U.S. (3 Cranch) 331 (1806).
55
Id. at 332 (emphasis omitted).
56
Id. at 337.
57
Id.
58
22 U.S. (9 Wheat.) 738 (1824).
59
Id. at 870.
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 17 21-MAR-12 13:28
148 NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:132
that law did violate the Contracts Clause, the defendants were person-
ally enjoined.
60
The Court was unwavering in its application of the enumeration
principle,
61
even in the face of honest mistakes.
62
The strength of its
application was best stated in Woolsey v. Dodge: “There is no axiom
of the law better established than this. A void law can afford no justifi-
cation to any one who acts under it . . . .”
63
The enumeration principle guided state supreme courts as well.
Perhaps the most interesting and straightforward example came from
the Civil War indemnity acts.
64
One of them, the 1863 Act, provided
that
any order of the President, or under his authority, made at any time
during the existence of the present rebellion, shall be a defence in
all courts to any action or prosecution, civil or criminal, pending, or
to be commenced, for any search, seizure, arrest, or imprisonment,
made, done, or committed, or acts omitted to be done, under and by
virtue of such order, or under color of any law of Congress.
65
This was impossible without abandoning the enumeration principle
and, with it, the concept of popular sovereignty. While the Court did
not have the opportunity to review the indemnity acts,
66
the Supreme
Court of Indiana held the statute unconstitutional because it
60
83 U.S. (16 Wall.) 203 (1872).
61
See, e.g., Bates v. Clark, 95 U.S. 204 (1877) (upholding a damages verdict for trespass
against an army captain and lieutenant who were following seizure orders given from an
United States Attorney). There, the Court reasoned:
[M]ilitary officers can no more protect themselves than civilians in time of
peace by orders emanating from a source which is itself without authority. . . .
So the plea that they had good reason to believe that this was Indian country,
and that they acted in good faith, while it might excuse these officers from
punitory damages, is no defence to the action. . . . [T]heir honest belief that
they had is no defence in their case more than in any other, where a party
mistaking his rights commits a trespass by forcibly seizing and taking away
another man’s property.
Id. at 209.
62
See, for example, Amy v. Supervisors, 78 U.S. (11 Wall.) 136 (1870), in which the
Court stated:
The rule is well settled, that where the law requires absolutely a ministerial act
to be done by a public officer, and he neglects or refuses to do such act, he may
be compelled to respond in damages to the extent of the injury arising from his
conduct. There is an unbroken current of authorities to this effect. A mistake
as to his duty and honest intentions will not excuse the offender.
Id. at 138; see also Developments in the Law—Remedies Against the United States and Its
Officials, 70 H
ARV
. L. R
EV
. 827, 836 n.51 (1957) (summarizing this point).
63
Woolsey v. Dodge, 30 F.Cas. 606, 607 (C.C. Ohio 1854), aff’d, 59 U.S. 331 (1856).
64
See Engdahl, supra note 43, at 48–50 (citing and discussing the indemnity acts in the
context of sovereign immunity).
65
Act of March 3, 1863, ch. 81 § 4, 12 Stat. 755, 756.
66
Engdhal, supra note 43, at 50.
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 18 21-MAR-12 13:28
April 2012] THE PATH OF THE CONSTITUTION 149
attempted to immunize and therefore authorize, something the
Constitution never gave the government power to do.
67
There seemed
to be no authorities in antebellum America that contradicted the enu-
meration principle, or even called its wisdom into question. But that
soon changed.
II
E
ROSION OF
C
OMMON
L
AW
R
EMEDIES
Part I introduced how common law remedies combined with the
enumeration principle to implement constitutional rights. Part II
describes how this system was disrupted, as common law remedies
began to wither both doctrinally and practically so as to threaten the
constitutional rights that the remedies once protected. This break-
down set the stage for the Supreme Court’s response, which is dis-
cussed in Part III.
America in the 1870s was a union of communities, “a nation of
loosely connected islands,” where even cities “retained much of the
town’s flavor.”
68
Below this world, there was another nation inhabited
by European immigrants, Chinese workers, migratory workers, and,
of course, those who by overdue fortunes of history were suddenly
experiencing the realities of their emancipation proclaimed. More and
more, economic forces began whirling American society, exposing the
different worlds to one another and, in the process, challenging the
coherence of communities. By the 1880s, the nation was deep in the
midst of transformation; as one historian put it, “[a]n age never lent
itself more readily to sweeping, uniform description: nationalization,
industrialization, mechanization, urbanization.”
69
These trends created others. The breakdown of local communi-
ties, an integrating economy, exponentially increasing crime rates,
growing state and federal bureaucracies, and growing police forces—
local and state at first, and, with Prohibition, federal—all placed enor-
mous stress on the common law system of remedying constitutional
harms. These factors worked to increase the number of interactions
between individuals and their government and, correspondingly, the
number of constitutional transgressions. In 1924, one scholar
described the “unexampled expansion of the police power in the
United States” as increasing the costs of “defective, negligent, per-
67
Id. (quoting Griffin v. Wilcox, 21 Ind. 370, 372–73 (1863)).
68
R
OBERT
H. W
IEBE
, T
HE
S
EARCH FOR
O
RDER
1877–1920, at 3, 4 (1967).
69
Id. at 12. See generally id. at 44–75 (describing social and economic dynamics that
undermined the traditional structures of American communities).
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 19 21-MAR-12 13:28
150 NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:132
verse or erroneous administration” of government functions.
70
As
more constitutional rights were violated (or as more people claimed
that they were), the remedial system was called to do more and more
work.
Under this stress, the common law system of remedies, long
assumed to be the vehicle by which the Constitution would be
enforced,
71
began to contract and fragment in ways that were inconsis-
tent with constitutional law and policy. The first was an increasing
trend toward affording officers immunity from damages.
72
Second, the
common law remedies withered to practically nil, in part because
plaintiffs were increasingly unsympathetic before local juries. Third,
new technologies, such as telephones and wiretapping, implicated con-
stitutional rights that did not give rise to causes of action (and there-
fore remedies) at common law.
A. Officer Immunity
As Part I demonstrated, the original system of common law rem-
edies for constitutional rights depended on holding officers liable for
actions that were inconsistent with the authority granted to govern-
ment by the Constitution. The whole point of the enumeration prin-
ciple was that the government could not authorize actions inconsistent
with the Constitution. It is not difficult to see how that system—the
marriage of common law remedies with the enumeration principle—
would be existentially threatened by officer immunity for unconstitu-
tional actions. Immunization is an important form of authorization.
70
Edward M. Borchard, Government Liability in Tort, 34 Y
ALE
L.J. 1, 1 (1924). Of
course, that trend has continued over time. For example, in 2002, the New York City Police
Department stopped, questioned, and sometimes frisked approximately 98,000 people. In
2004, the number was over 300,000, and by 2009, the number had reached 575,000. In 2002,
numbers from the New York Attorney General’s Office revealed that for every nine
people stopped, one person was arrested. Today, that ratio has doubled, counting eighteen
stops for every arrest. Over eighty percent of those being stopped were people of color,
and in some districts, the odds of any given resident being stopped in a year was roughly
one in three. N
EW
Y
ORK
P
OLICE
D
EP
T
, NYPD S
TOP
, Q
UESTION
,
AND
F
RISK
R
EPORT
D
ATABASE
, http://www.nyc.gov/html/nypd/html/analysis_and_planning/stop_question_and
_frisk_report.shtml (last visited Feb. 8, 2012).
71
For one of many sources on this, see, for example, Bradford P. Wilson, The Fourth
Amendment as More than a Form of Words: The View from the Founding, in T
HE
B
ILL OF
R
IGHTS
: O
RIGINAL
M
EANING AND
C
URRENT
U
NDERSTANDING
151 (Eugene W. Hickok,
Jr. ed., 1991). As Wilson describes, “[t]here is no reason to believe that the draftsmen of
the Constitution gave specific attention to the problems of implementation. . . . [T]he
Constitution was to be implemented in accordance with the remedial institutions of the
common law.” Id. at 156 (quoting Alfred Hill, Constitutional Remedies, 69 C
OLUM
. L. R
EV
.
1109, 1131–32 (1969)).
72
This Article does not discuss claims of expanding sovereign immunity made by
Engdahl and others. The focus here is on expanding immunity for officers personally.
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 20 21-MAR-12 13:28
April 2012] THE PATH OF THE CONSTITUTION 151
Indeed, immunization means that government is allowing its officer to
act unlawfully without being held liable. This Section discusses how
such immunization increasingly came to threaten the original system
of constitutional remedies.
There is a certain philosophy or attitude that underlies a regime
where officers are held strictly liable for unconstitutional acts even
when doing so in good faith or in the context of following orders.
Indeed, this regime may seem jarring to laypersons and lawyers today.
As mentioned earlier, while such potential unfairness gave Chief
Justice Marshall pause in Little v. Barreme, ultimately he (and courts
throughout the nineteenth century) believed that the question was to
be decided legally, as opposed to morally.
73
As one court put it, the
officer’s view of the constitutionality of a statute “is, in a legal point of
view, of no consequence.”
74
Eventually, however, scholars began to question this regime as a
fiction,
75
and often an unfair one. One scholar put it plainly: “If the
legislature enacts a statute which it has no power to enact, or does so
in a manner forbidden to it, the inferior officers in the judicial and
administrative branches of the government should not pay for the mis-
take.”
76
As the twentieth century progressed, commentators began to
share this apprehension.
77
As notions of fairness began to compete
with a rigorous application of the formal ultra vires logic, the doctrine
of officer liability wavered, and the enumeration principle seemed
threatened.
73
See supra notes 52–53 and accompanying text (describing Justice Marshall’s moral
ambivalence regarding the legal outcome in Barreme).
74
Clark v. Miller, 54 N.Y. 528, 532 (1874) (disregarding the view shared by both defen-
dant and officer that a law was unconstitutional) (emphasis added).
75
See, e.g., Kenneth Culp Davis, Suing the Government by Falsely Pretending To Sue
an Officer, 29 U. C
HI
. L. R
EV
. 435, 435–38 (1962) (describing officer liability as a false
pretense for suing the government).
76
Oliver P. Field, The Effect of an Unconstitutional Statute in the Law of Public
Officers: Liability of Officer for Action or Nonaction, 77 U. P
A
. L. R
EV
. 155, 188 (1929).
77
See, e.g., Oliver P. Field, Effect of an Unconstitutional Statute, 100 C
ENT
. L.J. 145, 150
(1927) (“After all, does it not seem sound to give private individuals and ministerial
officers the benefit of the view that statutes are to be obeyed until they are declared uncon-
stitutional?”); Jerry L. Mashaw, Civil Liability of Government Officers: Property Rights
and Official Accountability, 42 L
AW
& C
ONTEMP
. P
ROBS
. 8, 15 (1978) (referring to the
regime of officer liability as based on “draconian principles”); Max P. Rapacz, Protection
of Officers Who Act Under Unconstitutional Statutes, 11 M
INN
. L. R
EV
. 585, 603 (1927) (“It
is unfair and socially undesirable that the subordinate officers of the government should
assume the risk of constitutionality of legislative enactments.”); cf. Fleming James, Jr., Tort
Liability of Governmental Units and Their Officers, 22 U. C
HI
. L. R
EV
. 610, 615 (1955)
(noting a declining willingness of scholars and commentators to “defend the full extent of
governmental immunity” today, but doing so in a broader field of immunity than that con-
ferred for acting under authority of an unconstitutional law).
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 21 21-MAR-12 13:28
152 NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:132
Officer immunity rose from murky origins. Its history is notori-
ously complex,
78
and scholars have stumbled in telling it.
79
I tread
wearily into that thicket, thread in hand, stepping no farther than nec-
essary to demonstrate that the increasing complexity and prominence
of common law officer immunity had significant implications for the
adjudication of constitutional rights.
80
In 1791, official immunities were narrow and precisely selected.
81
For example, the common law provided varying forms of immunity to
judges acting within the scope of their jurisdiction.
82
A more promi-
nent example of immunity found express articulation in Article I,
Section 6, Clause 1 of the Constitution: “[F]or any Speech or Debate
in either House, [United States Senators and Representatives] shall
not be questioned in any other place.”
83
The idea here is simple:
Immunity is necessary both to encourage political discussion and
ensuing legislative activity and to discourage politically motivated
arrests.
84
78
See, e.g., Mashaw, supra note 77, at 10 (“[The] tale [of officer immunity] is indeed
long and ultimately ambiguous: the plot reflects a judicial preference for Joyce and Beckett
over Lardner and Twain.”).
79
Some of the best accounts are in Ann Woolhandler, Patterns of Official Immunity
and Accountability, 37 C
ASE
W. R
ES
. L. R
EV
. 396 (1986), and Jaffe, supra note 43.
80
As a preliminary matter, however, it is important to distinguish conceptually sover-
eign immunity from officer immunity. Sovereign immunity is a jurisdictional bar against
haling states into court without their consent. A suit against an officer should be dismissed
on grounds of sovereign immunity only if there is no cause of action against the officer
personally. See, e.g., Hans v. Louisiana, 134 U.S. 1, 21–22 (1890) (dismissing suit on
grounds of sovereign immunity because the contract was between plaintiff and State of
Louisiana). See generally Kian, supra note 37 (describing common law foundations of Hans
v. Louisiana). If a suit against a government official survives sovereign immunity—that is,
if the plaintiff spells out a cause of action against the individual defendant—officer immu-
nity may stand as a hurdle against recovery for the plaintiff. Officer immunity is a mis-
leading term insofar as it implies the doctrine is tied to personal jurisdiction. The officer is
not immune from being sued; rather, she is privileged against damage awards. While sover-
eign immunity withholds jurisdiction, officer immunity provides the officer with immunity
against damages.
81
See generally Engdahl, supra note 43, at 41–47 (reviewing official immunities).
82
See, e.g., Pierson v. Ray, 386 U.S. 547, 553–54 (1967) (“Few doctrines were more
solidly established at common law than the immunity of judges from liability for damages
for acts committed within their judicial jurisdiction.”). This immunity extended to a judge’s
decision about whether the court has jurisdiction, a somewhat entertaining recursion, but
any injury imposed by erroneous determinations can usually be allayed by the possibility of
appeal. See, e.g., Engdahl, supra note 43, at 43–47 (discussing application of judicial immu-
nity rule in various contexts where the bounds of jurisdiction are unclear).
83
U.S. C
ONST
. art. I, § 6, cl. 1.
84
Kilbourn v. Thompson, 103 U.S. 168 (1880), demonstrates how the contours of this
privilege are limited to lawmakers in their legislative capacities. There, the plaintiff had
sued members of the House for passing a resolution holding him in contempt. Though the
House lacked power to imprison the plaintiff, the Court held that official privilege pro-
tected the legislators from suit for false imprisonment. Id. at 205. Their unconstitutional
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 22 21-MAR-12 13:28
April 2012] THE PATH OF THE CONSTITUTION 153
By the 1920s, however, states had begun expanding official immu-
nity to executive officers. This expansion happened slowly, perhaps
equitably, and almost without regard for the consequences that such
immunities would have on enforcing individual rights. All of this, but
not unnoticed.
85
The scholarly consensus is that officer immunity deci-
sively superseded the earlier regime of liability.
86
Prior to 1880 there
was nigh “absolute uniformity in holding officers liable for injuries
resulting from the enforcement of unconstitutional acts.”
87
But, by the
mid-twentieth century, “the so-called ‘common law’ notion of privi-
lege for executive officials was being endorsed by the most reputable
judges and scholars, and the whole line of American precedents to the
contrary had been virtually forgotten.”
88
Scholars, commenting on the
rise in crime and full-time police bureaucracies, also noted a “consid-
erable growth in law designed to increase the protection of society by
officials.”
89
The broader trend was noted in contemporary torts
treatises:
Even as to officers acting under an unconstitutional statute, which
can confer no jurisdiction at all, the courts are being driven slowly to
the view that the officer cannot be required to determine legal ques-
tions which would perplex a court, and that if he has acted in good
faith he must not be liable.
90
Indeed, that same treatise, decades later, spoke even more confidently
about that trend:
The more modern and better reasoned cases, with many still to the
contrary, have extended this [immunity] even to the protection of
officers who act under statutes subsequently declared to be uncon-
stitutional, reasoning that the mentality of the average policeman,
whose life is traditionally not a happy one, should not be charged
with the decisions of questions which baffle the best lawyers in the
land.
91
enactment, however, did not protect the officer—John Thompson, Sergeant-at-Arms for
the House—who took the plaintiff into custody. He was without defense and liable for
damages. Id. Congress subsequently reimbursed Mr. Thompson. See Act of Mar. 3, 1885,
ch. 359, 23 Stat. 446, 467 (providing for Thompson’s reimbursement “for expenses, labor,
and attention in respect to the said case”).
85
For examples of scholars pointing out this trend, see generally Field, supra note 76
and Rapacz, supra note 77.
86
Engdahl, supra note 43, at 52.
87
Rapacz, supra note 77, at 585.
88
Engdahl, supra note 43, at 52.
89
Jerome Hall, The Law of Arrest in Relation to Contemporary Social Problems, 3 U.
C
HI
. L. R
EV
. 345, 363 (1935).
90
W
ILLIAM
L. P
ROSSER
, H
ANDBOOK OF THE
L
AW O F
T
ORTS
§ 25, at 153–54 (1941)
(emphasis added).
91
W
ILLIAM
L. P
ROSSER
, H
ANDBOOK OF THE
L
AW O F
T
ORTS
§ 25, at 128 (4th ed. 1971).
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 23 21-MAR-12 13:28
154 NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:132
The growth of immunity was no doubt real, but its implications for
enforcing constitutional rights were overstated. The reason is that
immunity grew mostly for when the officer was acting within the scope
of constitutionally permissible discretion. That kind of immunity—
whatever its merits—is not relevant here. What is relevant, however,
is that such immunity spilled over and was increasingly asserted with
success against claims that an officer was acting unconstitutionally.
92
The source of confusion lies primarily in the distinction between
unauthorized acts and discretionary acts,
93
famously discussed in
Marbury v. Madison.
94
The distinction is actually quite intuitive. The
government may do many things that harm individuals—for example,
tax them or enact bad policies—but there is a distinction between
harms that the Constitution allows the government to impose and
those that the government has no power to impose. In other words,
there is a difference between bad policy and unconstitutional law. The
enumeration principle, strictly applied, allows no justification for the
latter, but has nothing to say about the former.
This principle drove the distinction in Marbury. On the one hand,
where the “executive possesses a constitutional or legal discretion,
nothing can be more perfectly clear than that their acts are only politi-
cally examinable”
95
—that is, like a misguided tax policy, any conse-
quences or injuries flowing from the exercise of a legally authorized
discretion can only be remedied politically.
96
Read properly, this
means that officers cannot be held liable for acting within the realm of
discretion contemplated by law.
97
On the other hand, “where a spe-
cific duty is assigned by law, and individual rights depend upon the
performance of that duty, it seems equally clear that the individual
who considers himself injured, has a right to resort to the laws of his
92
The argument in the next Section is that the Court’s jurisprudence accounted for the
fact that growing officer immunities weakened common-law remedies and thus deflated
constitutional rights. For this narrative to be true, it is not entirely necessary that officer
immunities actually grow; rather, it is sufficient that jurists perceive immunities as growing
and thus threatening constitutional rights.
93
See, e.g., Kendall v. Stokes, 44 U.S. (3 How.) 87, 98 (1845) (holding that a “public
officer” cannot be held liable “where the act to be done is not merely a ministerial one, but
is one in relation to which it is his duty to exercise judgment and discretion; even although
an individual may suffer by his mistake”); William C. Mathes & Robert T. Jones, Toward a
“Scope of Official Duty” Immunity for Police Officers in Damage Actions, 53 G
EO
. L.J.
889, 896–97 (1965) (discussing this distinction).
94
5 U.S. (1 Cranch) 137, 166 (1803).
95
Id. Alternatively, the plaintiff has a claim against the State, which cannot be sued
unless it waives sovereign immunity.
96
See F
REDERICK
P
OLLOCK
, A T
REATISE ON THE
L
AW O F
T
ORTS
157–58 (3d ed. 1894)
(discussing immunity for discretionary actions in the absence of negligence).
97
See, e.g., Engdahl, supra note 43, at 48 (discussing this principle in the context of
later cases).
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 24 21-MAR-12 13:28
April 2012] THE PATH OF THE CONSTITUTION 155
country for a remedy.”
98
The distinction is between cases where an
officer has discretion and where he does not.
99
There is theoretically
nothing besides the two sides of the immunity/liability coin: immunity
for acting within the appropriate bounds of discretion, strict liability
for acting outside of the authority enumerated by the Constitution.
100
Scholars have treated immunity for discretionary actions as per-
mitting that which the enumeration principle forbids: immunity for
doing something prohibited by the Constitution.
101
But the cases cited
throughout the scholarship generally do not stand for the proposition
that an officer is immune even when injuring someone in accordance
with an unconstitutional statute.
102
The question they ask is whether
98
Marbury, 5 U.S. (1 Cranch) at 166.
99
Scholars and treatises have protested this dichotomy, at least in its later applications,
as conceptually incoherent, “a way of stating rather than arriving at the result,” and “a
convenient device for extending the area of nonliablity without making the reasons
explicit.” Louis L. Jaffe, Suits Against Governments and Officers: Damage Actions, 77
H
ARV
. L. R
EV
. 209, 218 (1963); see also P
ROSSER
, supra note 90, § 25, at 151–53 (1941)
(labeling this distinction “rather artificial and scarcely justifiable”).
It need not be incoherent, at least for purposes of understanding officer immunity.
There are two sources of law that limit an officer’s realm of discretion so as to render his
actions “ministerial” rather than “discretionary.” First, a statute may provide an officer
with particular, nondiscretionary duties. For example, in one case, city jailers were required
to “keep the jail clean and well ventilated, and in good sanitary condition at all times, and
free from bugs and vermin . . . with a bed and bedding cleanly and sufficient . . . .” Clark v.
Kelly, 133 S.E. 365, 369 (W. Va. 1926). The West Virginia court held that these were “all
positive duties,” not discretionary, and thus the jailer was “‘liable in damages to any one
specially injured either by his omitting to perform the task or duty, or by his performing it
negligently or unskillfully.’Id. (quoting Henderson v. Smith, 26 W. Va. 829 (1885)).
Second, all government action is limited by the Constitution. Regardless of other obliga-
tions, an officer can never have discretion to violate the Constitution—any such action is
per se unauthorized, and exposes the officer to liability under the common law.
100
There is an important distinction between statutory authority and constitutional
authority. Statutory rights can be limited by officer immunity—this just amounts to
granting narrower statutory rights. Therefore, the West Virginia law mentioned in the pre-
vious footnote could, by judicial gloss or legislative amendment, be read to require a clean
jail, yet immunize officers for their negligence in providing that cleanliness. At that point,
there would be a right (to a clean jail), but no remedy against the officer. But of course,
statutory immunity would not protect him from actions that violate the Constitution, if any
were committed. This is because there is no legislative authority to authorize unconstitu-
tional actions by immunizing those who commit them.
101
See, e.g., Mathes & Jones, supra note 93, at 912 (not distinguishing between the two
ideas in concluding that “the expansion of the official immunity doctrine in recent times
makes individual police-officer liability more the exception . . . to what is really a general
rule of public officer immunity”); Mashaw, supra note 77, at 8 (discussing liability without
sensitivity to this distinction).
102
To argue otherwise, prominent authorities cite a decision by the Iowa Supreme
Court, Henke v. McCord, 7 N.W. 623 (Iowa 1880), as “the leading case” in support of the
view that officers should not be liable for injuries resulting from enforcement of unconsti-
tutional statutes. Rapacz, supra note 77, at 591–92. See also P
ROSSER
, supra note 90, § 25,
at 154 n.84 (citing Henke for the proposition that “if [the officer] has acted in good faith he
must not be liable”); Field, supra note 76, at 185–90 (drawing on case law in discussing
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 25 21-MAR-12 13:28
156 NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:132
the officer has valid discretion to commit the precise action that alleg-
edly harmed the plaintiff—that is, whether the discretion exercised
was within the bounds of authority conferred to the government by
the Constitution. If the answer is yes, it follows that no constitutional
injury has been suffered, insofar as the judiciary is concerned.
103
But scholars were not entirely wrong. As officer immunity grew,
it spilled over into protecting officers who acted unconstitutionally.
Some states, like California, went as far as providing such officers with
statutory immunity.
104
Whereas precedent from the antebellum period
when officers should be subject to suit for acting on unconstitutional statutes). Rapacz’s
view is not entirely clear, as he cites Henke for this proposition, Rapacz, supra note 77, at
585–86, but later implies its shortcomings, id. at 594. The case does not support that view,
at least not when put in its specific legal context. In Henke, a justice of the peace had
issued a search-and-seizure warrant in accordance with a municipal ordinance, and a mar-
shal acted on the warrant and seized the plaintiff’s property. Henke, 7 N.W. at 623. The
Iowa Supreme Court, surprisingly, determined that the ordinance authorizing such war-
rants was “void for want of authority of the municipal corporation to enact them” but went
on to find that both the justice of the peace and the marshal were immune from liability.
Id. at 625.
Two wrinkles, neither novel in American legal tradition, explain this case. First, judges
have been historically afforded immunity for acting within their jurisdiction and capacity as
judges. Second, a historically-accepted ancillary immunity has been available for a seizure
that meets two conditions: (1) having been “issued by a court or officer having authority of
law to issue such process,” and there have been (2) “nothing on the face of the process
apprising the officer to whom it [was] delivered for service, that in the particular case there
was no authority for issuing it.” T
HOMAS
M. C
OOLEY
, A T
REATISE ON THE
L
AW O F
T
ORTS
OR THE
W
RONGS
W
HICH
A
RISE
I
NDEPENDENT OF
C
ONTRACT
199 (2d ed. 1888). In line
with this, the court in Henke premised the marshal’s immunity on the fact that the justice
had jurisdiction to issue the warrant, which was “regular on its face.” Henke, 7 N.W. at 626.
This is not inconsistent with the officer liability regime discussed earlier. See supra
notes 82–84 and accompanying text. Here, when sued, the marshal could indeed point to a
valid authority: a warrant issued by a court of competent jurisdiction. That the court, prop-
erly exercising jurisdiction, erred in its legal conclusion about the ordinance was not mate-
rial. The officer was not relying on the unconstitutional or void statute, but rather on the
validly issued warrant. In other words, the warrant, issued by a competent court and not
erroneous on its face, did confer authority to the officer for the seizure. Persuasive or not,
this was not a new distinction—indeed, it was inherent to the separation of powers—and
posed no threat to the enumeration principle at large. The Court would later build this
exception into the exclusionary rule. See United States v. Leon, 468 U.S. 897, 926 (1984)
(expanding the exception where officers had relied on a seemingly valid warrant as the
exclusionary rule’s purposes would “only rarely be served by applying it” in such cases).
103
Of course, the plaintiff could pursue any number of political remedies such as peti-
tioning Congress. P
OLLOCK
, supra note 96, at 155 (“[T]he remedy of the party who suffers
the loss is confined to recovering such compensation . . . as the Legislature has thought fit
to give him.”).
104
According to the California Civil Code:
A State, county, district or municipal officer . . . or any officer, agent, or
employee of any political subdivision, acting in good faith and without malice
under the apparent authority of any law of this State, whether enacted by the
Legislature or by the people of the State through initiative action, which law
subsequently is judicially declared unconstitutional, as in conflict with the
Constitution of this State or of the United States, shall not be held civilly liable
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 26 21-MAR-12 13:28
April 2012] THE PATH OF THE CONSTITUTION 157
held officers liable for serving process under an unconstitutional
statute—recall the Sergeant-at-Arms in Kilbournthe weight of state
court authority had significantly shifted by the 1920s.
105
Other cases
simply contradicted the enumeration principle. For example, in Dexter
v. Alfred, the plaintiff sued a town’s highway commissioner for cutting
fallen trees on his land, removing them from roads, and laying out a
“public highway across the lands mentioned in the plaintiff’s com-
plaint.”
106
Notwithstanding a century of precedent otherwise, the New
York court held that the defendant could claim an unconstitutional
statute as his defense:
The defendant, in his answer in this case, undertakes to justify or
mitigate the alleged trespass committed by him . . . on the ground
that the commissioner of highways was acting under and in pursu-
ance of the provisions of this act, while it was in force, and before it
was adjudged to be unconstitutional, and that the defendant was
acting under the orders of the commissioner. It was no part of the
duty of the commissioner of highways to decide whether the law in
question was or was not constitutional. His duty was to execute the
law as he found it.
107
To reach this result, the court cited an earlier New York case
asserting that “[u]nder our system of government no power is given to
public officers to refuse or suspend their obedience to laws on any
opinion of their own that a law is unconstitutional.”
108
There, how-
ever, the court was reasserting a well-established principle designed
for a slightly different context: An officer is liable for refusing to act
under authority he believes to be unconstitutional if the authority in
fact constitutionally imposed a non-discretionary duty on the
officer.
109
The view in Dexter, while increasingly common throughout the
states,
110
was by no means uniform, not even in New York, which
in any action in which he would not have been liable if such law had not been
declared unconstitutional, nor shall he be liable to any greater extent than he
would have been if such law had not been declared unconstitutional.
C
AL
. C
IV
. C
ODE
§ 3342 (1933). To my knowledge, the constitutionality of this immunity
was not tested.
105
Field, supra note 76, at 180 (noting the shift in state court authority by writing about
contemporaneous developments in the law regarding officer liability).
106
Dexter v. Alfred, 19 N.Y.S. 770, 770 (1892).
107
Id. at 771.
108
Clark v. Miller, 54 N.Y. 528, 532 (1874).
109
Id.; see also Field, supra note 76, at 158–65 (summarizing similar cases regarding an
officer’s refusal to act).
110
Another notable example is Goodwin v. Guild, 29 S.W. 722 (Tenn. 1895). There, the
Tennessee court reasoned:
While we would not be understood as going to this length, still it will not do to
apply the same strict rules of liability to an executive officer, whose duty it is to
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 27 21-MAR-12 13:28
158 NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:132
floundered from case to case.
111
For example, cases almost uniformly
held officers liable when dealing with unconstitutional taxes or war-
rantless arrests conducted under unconstitutional statutes.
112
However, even in the latter cases, state courts expanded officer immu-
nity by massaging other doctrines to that end. For example, the
common law rule was that officers were liable for warrantless arrests
unless they could otherwise point to a felony or breach of the
peace.
113
Courts gave more robust interpretations to those exceptions
in order to confer immunity on officers making otherwise illegal
arrests. For example, courts began interpreting traditional misde-
meanors to be felonies in order to legalize arrests made without a war-
rant.
114
Moreover, in many jurisdictions, a conviction became “a
complete defense to an action of false arrest or imprisonment, on the
ground that it establishes a conclusive presumption of probable
cause.”
115
And that was the trend, overstated but increasingly true.
116
see the laws executed, if he makes a mistake in judgment, that would be
applied to an individual who has no public duty to perform in executing its
laws. To hold this strict rule would paralyze the arm of every executive and
peace officer; and while such officer, for any wanton or malicious abuse of
legal process which is set on foot for the oppression of a citizen, must be held
liable to the same, or possibly a greater, extent than a private individual, still
there must be undoubted evidence of malice, oppression, and wanton persecu-
tion, with the absence of all probable cause or excuse, to hold a public official
liable for errors in the execution of his official duties.
Id. at 723; cf. Shafford v. Brown, 95 P. 270, 271 (Wash. 1908) (upholding the defendant’s
demurrer on the grounds that he was “acting in good faith under a statute of the
Legislature [and] . . . doubtless supposed it to be a valid statute”); Lang v. Mayor of
Bayonne, 68 A. 90, 93 (N.J. 1907) (“Every law of the Legislature, however repugnant to
the Constitution, has not only the appearance and semblance of authority, but the force of
law.”); Field, supra note 76, at 167–70 (similar). See generally Rapacz, supra note 77 (dis-
cussing similar cases).
111
See, e.g., Saratoga State Waters Corp. v. Pratt, 125 N.E. 834 (N.Y. 1920) (granting an
injunction against state officers to prevent them from interfering with the plaintiff’s land,
and awarding damages to compensate for past interferences with that land); see also Field,
supra note 77, at 156–57 (summarizing the state of the law with regard to the effect of
unconstitutional statutes).
112
Field, supra note 76, at 166–67, 170–73.
113
See, e.g., Tillman v. Beard, 80 N.W. 248, 248 (Mich. 1899) (referring to this proposi-
tion as so “elementary” that “[i]t is needless to cite authorities”).
114
Id. This marked a shift away from the Restatement’s position. Caleb Foote, Tort
Remedies for Police Violations of Individual Rights, 39 M
INN
. L. R
EV
. 493, 504 n.65 (1954).
115
Foote, supra note 114, at 506.
116
This trend continues today. For example, the Indiana Supreme Court recently held
that “a right to resist an unlawful police entry into a home is against public policy and is
incompatible with modern Fourth Amendment jurisprudence . . . .” Barnes v. Indiana, 946
N.E.2d 572, 576 (Ind. 2011), thus admittedly abandoning the “common-law right to resist
unlawful police action [that has] existed for over three hundred years, and [which] some
scholars trace . . . to the Magna Carta in 1215.” Id. at 575. Of course, this violates the
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 28 21-MAR-12 13:28
April 2012] THE PATH OF THE CONSTITUTION 159
B. Pragmatics
The common law remedies also withered practically. Over time,
the prospect of actual monetary recovery diminished, sinking with it
the prospect of continuing to enforce the Constitution through state
common law. It seems obvious that constitutional rights are
threatened by a regime where officers are prohibited from acting
unconstitutionally but face no actual cost when they do so. This phe-
nomenon, despite being a critical change in how constitutional rights
are enforced, has received little empirical attention, and this Article
does not fill that gap.
117
Rather, it is sufficient for the Article’s pur-
poses to highlight the problem and the fact that scholars recognized it.
As the traditional remedy grew inadequate, the pressure to compen-
sate increased.
The seminal work here is an article by Caleb Foote, who
describes in some detail the practical challenges facing plaintiffs suing
officers.
118
There are two challenges worth recapitulating. First, in
order to remedy adequately the violation of constitutional rights, the
law must conceive of damages rather broadly. This is how it used to
be: Jurisdictions would allow for recovery of punitive damages, and
the jury was given “wide scope in attaching a dollar value to
immeasurables such as the sense of humiliation, distress, disgrace or
outrage, or the usually fictional damages to reputation.”
119
But that
changed, even where officer immunities were not triggered. Those suf-
fering from illegal searches and false imprisonment
120
—where the
officer detained and searched the individual without any valid
enumeration principle unless the same rule applies to all intruders—in which case no one
could use reasonable force against any unlawful intruder. To give the officer special legal
protection in this context violates the Fourth Amendment, which stands for the proposition
that the government is not authorized to unlawfully search or seize and thus, when it does,
the perpetrating officer can enjoy no legal privilege and will be treated as any other indi-
vidual trespasser. The core result of the enumeration principle is that when an officer does
something unconstitutional, he will be treated like any other person. On a different front,
the trend also manifests itself today in the ever-broadening privileges to which members of
government believe themselves entitled. See, e.g., Lacey, supra note 40 (recounting
instances where lawmakers claim immunity for drunk driving, domestic violence, and
speeding).
117
See, e.g., Alexander A. Reinert, Measuring the Success of Bivens Litigation and Its
Consequences for the Individual Liability Model, 62 S
TAN
. L. R
EV
. 809, 813 (2010) (repre-
senting “the first attempt to systematically study the success of Bivens litigations”).
118
Foote, supra note 114.
119
Id. at 497; see also, e.g., Entick v. Carrington, (1765) 95 Eng. Rep. 807 (K.B.) 807; 2
Wils. K.B. 275 (providing large sum of damages for trespass).
120
“False imprisonment” is a legal term of art that refers to “imposing, by force or
threats, an unlawful restraint upon a man’s freedom of locomotion.” T
HOMAS
M. C
OOLEY
,
A T
REATISE ON THE
L
AW O F
T
ORTS OR THE
W
RONGS
W
HICH
A
RISE
I
NDEPENDENTLY OF
C
ONTRACT
§ 80 (students’ ed. 1907).
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 29 21-MAR-12 13:28
160 NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:132
constitutional authority—found their lawsuits recovering little more
than a penny.
121
As Foote noted, by the 1950s, this trend had long
buried the trespass action and was beginning to overcome the false
imprisonment action as well.
122
The second challenge is related: The plaintiffs in such cases were
perceived as increasingly less sympathetic. Foote argues that this per-
ception was responsible for the declining damages awards. At one
level of abstraction, this is no doubt correct.
123
The jury’s perception
of the equities (or the judge’s, in a bench trial) had always been
implied in a system where constitutional remedies were enforced
through civil actions and, in particular, actions in tort law.
124
As the
twentieth century unfolded, those most often litigating their individual
rights against officers were of a different sort than the esteemed
merchants bringing trespass suits against British officers in the eight-
eenth century. Rather, they were criminals,
125
drug offenders, minori-
ties of various sorts, and strangers in increasingly estranged
121
See, e.g., Lowry v. Barker, 190 S.E. 341 (N.C. 1937) (affirming the jury’s award of
only one penny in suit against the officer for unlawful arrest, false imprisonment, assault,
and battery); Clements v. Canon, 40 P.2d 640 (Okla. 1935) (affirming the jury’s award of
one dollar for two unlawful arrests and false imprisonment lasting several hours in the first
instance and overnight in the second instance); McLean v. Sanders, 7 P.2d 981 (Or. 1932)
(reversing award of no damages where the jury found false imprisonment but awarded the
plaintiff nothing, because the verdict for the plaintiff should reward at least nominal dam-
ages lest it be considered a verdict for the defendant); Moore v. Duke, 80 A. 194 (Vt. 1911)
(reversing the punitive damages award of $19.33 and awarding the plaintiff one dollar for
the trespass action against the town constable); Foote, supra note 114, at 498–99 nn.33, 35
(citing two Maryland cases and a Louisiana case where nominal damages were awarded). It
is noteworthy that Maryland would have admitted the evidence recovered from such illegal
searches. See id. at 500 n.42 (citing a Kansas case where the court directed a verdict for the
defendant on the grounds that the plaintiff, having a prior criminal record, could not
recover damages for having been humiliated by false arrest).
122
Foote, supra note 114, at 499 (noting that if this trend continues “false imprisonment
will join trespass for illegal search in the graveyard of useless remedies”).
123
See, e.g., id. at 500 n.42 (providing an example of social stigma preventing recovery
for a plaintiff’s false imprisonment claim).
124
See, e.g., Ker v. Illinois, 119 U.S. 436, 444 (1886) (noting in dicta that whether one
could recover a sufficient sum by bringing a suit for trespass or false imprisonment “would
probably depend upon moral aspects of the case”).
125
Local evidence law was particularly relevant here, as defendants could present evi-
dence of “previous arrests and time spent in jail” for purposes of mitigating damages stem-
ming from humiliation and mental anguish. 35 C.J.S. False Imprisonment § 63 (2009). As
Foote noted, common law actions like false imprisonment are “successful as an inducement
to sue only for the respectable plaintiff who can come into court with relatively clean
hands.” Foote, supra note 114, at 500. It was particularly problematic for plaintiffs that if
the transgressions nonetheless resulted in a conviction, that conviction could “be shown to
impeach the plaintiff’s credibility as a witness.” Id. at 506. Moreover, those in prison often
“must wait until they are released to get their tort remedy.” Id. at 508.
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 30 21-MAR-12 13:28
April 2012] THE PATH OF THE CONSTITUTION 161
communities, citing liberties that were increasingly seen as in tension
with local security.
126
The result of these two factors is, as one court put it, that “cases
involving civil actions against police officers are rare and those
involving successful criminal prosecutions against officers are nonexis-
tent. In short, the constitutional provisions are not being enforced.”
127
As another noted, despite
general knowledge of the prohibition against unlawful search, it is
not an uncommon thing in this state, for officers of the law . . . to
disregard the law upon the assumption that the end sought to be
accomplished will justify the means, and therefore no attention
need be given to constitutional authority, when public approval will
commend the unlawful conduct.
128
C. The Common Law in a New World
Finally, it is worth noting that the common law’s conception of
actionable injuries did not keep in neat accord with those contem-
plated by the Constitution. The easiest example is Katz v. United
States, in which the Court found an actionable Fourth Amendment
injury in warrantless wiretapping.
129
Such an injury was not necessa-
rily a cognizable injury at common law.
130
Similar problems exist with
126
As an anecdotal matter, it is interesting to note that state cases grew more explicitly
cognizant of law enforcement values. See, e.g., Mason v. Wrightson, 109 A.2d 128, 129 (Md.
1954) (beginning opinion by noting Baltimore’s interest in “combat[ting] . . . lawlessness”);
Youman v. Commonwealth, 224 S.W. 860, 861 (Ky. 1920) (“[T]here appears to be a
growing public sentiment against the observance of or obedience to any constitutional
restraint that obstructs or stands in the way of the desires of [officers] who seek to accom-
plish their purposes . . . .”); cf. Brinegar v. United States, 338 U.S. 160, 183 (1949) (Jackson,
J., dissenting) (mentioning the difficulties that automobile searches presented for law
enforcement, and implying that the Court had become too sensitive to those difficulties).
127
People v. Cahan, 282 P.2d 905, 913 (Cal. 1955) (en banc), superseded by statute, C
AL
.
C
ONST
. art. I, § 28, pt. (d), as recognized in People v. Daan, 161 Cal. App. 3d 22, 26–27
(1984).
128
Youman, 224 S.W. at 861; see also Hoyer v. State, 193 N.W. 89, 93 (Wis. 1923) (refer-
ring to a trespass action against officers as “bootless and fruitless”).
129
389 U.S. 347 (1967).
130
The term “common law” is used to refer to the common law of the several states. Of
course the law varied by state, but the point here is that this fragmented approach frus-
trated the judicial enforcement of constitutional law. With dozens of different approaches,
the robustness of the Constitution’s protections in any given state became delegated to the
niceties of local common law. Thus, even scholars advocating a common law-esque
approach to the Fourth Amendment recognize that actions like wiretapping would have to
be cognizable. See, e.g., Akhil Reed Amar, Fourth Amendment First Principles, 107 H
ARV
.
L. R
EV
. 757, 798 (1994) [hereinafter Amar, Fourth Amendment] (characterizing wiretap-
ping as a modern supplement to the traditional trespass rule).
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 31 21-MAR-12 13:28
162 NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:132
countless other technologies, including, for example, the introduction
of photocopiers.
131
There was also the problem of the awkward fit between policies
pursued by the common law and those required by the Constitution,
which became particularly apparent with the civil rights movement.
For example, perhaps the common law would settle for damages paid
to those suffering from segregated schools (by viewing them as being
excluded from a property to which they rightfully have a license), but
the Constitution would not.
132
Integration was the mandate. These
kinds of tensions rendered the common law a less and less appealing
system by which to judicially enforce the Constitution, as they placed
constitutional rights valued one way at the whim of local common
laws that might value them in another.
III
R
ETHINKING
C
ORE
D
ECISIONS OF
C
ONSTITUTIONAL
I
MPLEMENTATION
Thus far, this Article has introduced the original system of
common law remedies and described how this system began to break
down. In the backdrop of these changes lurked federalism’s elephant:
the Civil War. As embodied in the Madisonian Compromise,
133
prior
to the Civil War states were generally believed to be the protectors of
constitutional rights. Thus, it made perfect sense for the common law
to provide remedies for violations of constitutional rights. But the
issue of slavery, the brutality of the Civil War, and the persistence of
racial prejudice through Jim Crow taught the nascent Republic that all
governments, whether state or federal, could pose a threat to liberty.
These developments fundamentally changed the perception of the
131
See Silverthorne Lumber Co. v. United States, 251 U.S. 385 (1920) (dealing with the
problem of police officers making photocopies of private documents that they were not
allowed to have). For a modern example, see generally Orin S. Kerr, Applying the Fourth
Amendment to the Internet: A General Approach, 62 S
TAN
. L. R
EV
. 1005 (2010). Professor
Kerr suggests that judges should distinguish between content and non-content information
and limit search warrants to individuals, rather than Internet accounts.
132
See Brown v. Bd. of Educ., 347 U.S. 483, 495 (1954) (requiring desegregation). Of
course, the proper analysis at common law would require injunctive relief here because
damages would be inadequate, but there was no guarantee that a state would arrive at this
conclusion. And that is the point: Leaving the enforcement of constitutional rights to the
common law creates a tension, particularly when common law policies are not in perfect
accord with the contours of constitutional rights.
133
That is, the founding agreement that Congress would have discretion over whether
to create federal courts other than the Supreme Court. See Amanda Frost, Overvaluing
Uniformity, 94 V
A
. L. R
EV
. 1567, 1620–22 (2008) (describing how the Madisonian
Compromise, in delegating to Congress the decision to create lower federal courts, com-
prehended the possibility that Congress would create no lower federal courts, thus leaving
the interpretation of federal law to state courts).
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 32 21-MAR-12 13:28
April 2012] THE PATH OF THE CONSTITUTION 163
federal government’s role in protecting individual rights, such that
federal courts were increasingly called into action. This made the
decline in common law remedies all the more significant.
There were two factors in particular that were consequential:
First, the growth of the federal government and the number of federal
officers, and second, the incorporation of the Bill of Rights. These
changes created a situation in which an exponentially increasing
potential for constitutional violations was left to a system of common
law remedies that no longer neatly aligned itself with the contours of
constitutional law and policy. This Part will examine how that dynamic
structured the Supreme Court’s response, in three cases: Mapp v.
Ohio,
134
Monroe v. Pape,
135
and Bivens v. Six Unknown Named
Agents.
136
There are two arguments to be made here. The first is more basic:
Simply looking at the relationship between common law remedies and
constitutional rights will yield interesting insights. The discussion of
the exclusionary rule that follows demonstrates this vividly. The
second point is more the focus of this Article: The weakening of
common law remedies discussed in Part II created a set of tensions
that the Court was forced to address. The thesis is not, however, that
the Court consciously undertook a project to revitalize constitutional
rights. It is, instead, more subtle: The weakening remedies actually
had doctrinal significance that in turn affected the salience and per-
suasiveness of the arguments that the Court ultimately adopted in
these three cases.
A. The Exclusionary Rule
There is hardly a constitutional debate more robust than that
inspired by the Fourth Amendment exclusionary rule.
137
The basic
idea behind the exclusionary rule is simple: Evidence obtained in vio-
lation of the Fourth Amendment will be inadmissible as evidence in a
criminal trial. Defenders of the exclusionary rule argue that it is the
only meaningful way to realize the Fourth Amendment right.
138
Detractors respond that the rule is judge made, extratextual, and
134
367 U.S. 643 (1961).
135
365 U.S. 167 (1961).
136
403 U.S. 388 (1971).
137
So robust, in fact, that contemporary scholarship begins with this proposition, then
cites the footnotes of previous articles making the same assertion. In that tradition, see
Yale Kamisar, The Writings of John Barker Waite and Thomas Davies on the Search and
Seizure Exclusionary Rule, 100 M
ICH
. L. R
EV
. 1821, 1821 n.3 (2002).
138
Some have argued that this intuition is in accord with history. For a particularly
exhaustive and recent example, see generally Roger Roots, The Originalist Case for the
Fourth Amendment Exclusionary Rule, 45 G
ONZ
. L. R
EV
. 1 (2010).
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 33 21-MAR-12 13:28
164 NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:132
simply bad policy. This debate has characterized the exclusionary rule
as a policy tool—a mere policy tool—drafted by the Court and
wielded to service the Fourth Amendment right.
139
Accordingly, the
Court has characterized the rule as “prudential rather than constitu-
tionally mandated,” and only applicable “where its deterrence bene-
fits outweigh its ‘substantial social costs.’
140
Scholarly discussion has
followed suit, as has legal education. Those interested in that debate
will not be disappointed by the quality of scholarship devoted to its
resolution, but this Article does not attempt to resolve these
disagreements.
The focus of this Article is to describe the exclusionary rule as
partly a consequence of the common law remedies discussed above.
Modern legal minds draw sharp distinctions between criminal and civil
law. Criminal procedure textbooks devote at most a few pages to the
relationship between criminal procedure and the common law, and
the pages they do devote frame common law remedies as yet another
alternative to the exclusionary rule. While that framework is not
incorrect,
141
it does not capture the intricate role that common law
remedies played in defining Fourth Amendment rights.
The following Sections operate in tandem to fill that gap. This
Article will first explain how various common law doctrines interacted
to generate the federal exclusionary rule. As it turns out, the federal
exclusionary rule was not a made-up policy crutch for the Fourth
Amendment right. The exclusionary rule actually came to being
through problems created by the enumeration principle’s core ques-
tion: Does the government have constitutional authority for what it is
doing? For example, if a court ordered an unreasonable seizure of a
139
See, e.g., Amar, Fourth Amendment, supra note 130, at 785 (characterizing the Court
as having “concocted the awkward and embarrassing remedy of excluding reliable evi-
dence of criminal guilt”); Randy E. Barnett, Resolving the Dilemma of the Exclusionary
Rule: An Application of Restitutive Principles of Justice, 32 E
MORY
L.J. 937, 939 (1983) (“A
remedy is needed that accomplishes the objectives of crime prevention and justice and that
deters police misconduct as well as or better than the exclusionary rule. The growing sup-
port for a weakening of the exclusionary rule by the creation of a so-called ‘good faith
exception’ may make it a propitious time for those concerned with deterring police miscon-
duct to pursue such an alternative vigorously.”); cf. Richard A. Posner, Excessive Sanctions
for Governmental Misconduct in Criminal Cases, 57 W
ASH
. L. R
EV
. 635, 646 (1982)
(arguing that courts “have been guided by concerns articulable, if rarely articulated, in
terms of economic efficiency”).
140
Pa. Bd. of Prob. & Parole v. Scott, 524 U.S. 357, 363 (1998) (quoting United States v.
Leon, 468 U.S. 897, 907 (1984)); see also Stone v. Powell, 428 U.S. 465, 489 (1976) (“The
answer [to the question of whether to apply the exclusionary rule] is to be found by
weighing the utility of the exclusionary rule against the costs of extending it to collateral
review of Fourth Amendment claims.”).
141
Indeed, we are not in the realm of incorrect versus correct. We are instead looking
for useful ways to understand what happened in the Fourth Amendment world.
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 34 21-MAR-12 13:28
April 2012] THE PATH OF THE CONSTITUTION 165
defendant’s papers, and the defendant objected, the enumeration
principle would require the objection to be upheld, because there is
no authority on which to uphold such an order.
A more familiar scenario is when an officer seizes evidence
before a trial has even begun. This, as the Article will demonstrate,
gets tricky. Suppose an officer unreasonably seizes a defendant’s
dagger and decides that he will hold the weapon until the government
prosecutes the defendant several months later. If, prior to the criminal
trial, the defendant were to sue the officer for return of his dagger, the
officer would need some sort of defense for why he could in fact keep
it. But if he acquired it by constitutionally-prohibited means, he would
have no defense. What he needs is a lawfully-acquired license to the
property. He could not say, “the government authorizes me to keep
evidence seized by means the Constitution prohibits,” because the
Constitution specifically denies the government that power.
As it turns out, the defendant has a cause of action in property
against the officer. But it is not that simple. Suppose the defendant
waits until the criminal trial and only then objects to the introduction
of the dagger as evidence. Historically, he would lose: Prosecutors and
officers are authorized to introduce evidence, and a criminal trial is
not the place to stop and sort out property rights. If the defendant had
a property claim, he could file that claim in another action, but he
could not do so in the middle of a criminal trial.
Eventually, what started as a rule of property became a rule of
evidence because of both the Fourth and Fifth Amendments. Below,
the first Section will trace this transformation and provide a nuanced
account of how the federal exclusionary rule came to be. The Section
that follows explains how the Court eventually incorporated the exclu-
sionary rule against the states.
The point of these two Sections is to illustrate how the path of
various constitutional rights was intimately shaped by the path of the
common law. As we go through this history, we should keep in mind
that common law remedies for constitutional rights have diminished
over time.
142
This is important because if constitutional rights are
shaped by the common law (which the next Section demonstrates in
the context of the exclusionary rule), then the dwindling availability of
common law remedies threatens to deflate constitutional rights.
This withering of remedies posed a major challenge to the Court:
To what extent could it allow changes in the common law to squeeze
constitutional rights? The Court had to decide if the common law was
142
See supra Part II (describing factors that led to the withering of common law
remedies).
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 35 21-MAR-12 13:28
166 NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:132
severable from constitutional law or if, to some extent, constitutional
law required the preservation of some common law remedies (perhaps
as necessary for due process of law). The second Section below
explains how the Court handled this problem in the context of incor-
porating the right against unreasonable searches and seizures. In
short, the Court “constitutionalized” the exclusionary rule, both in
federal and state courts, by making it a constitutional requirement
rather than a remedy available solely by virtue of state property law.
1. The Federal Exclusionary Rule
The assumption in Fourth Amendment scholarship
143
is that
Boyd v. United States
144
and Weeks v. United States
145
introduced the
exclusionary rule into federal practice, and these cases were later
incorporated against the states by Mapp v. Ohio.
146
Before these
cases, the story goes, there was no exclusionary rule and, in fact, the
exclusionary rule was specifically precluded by the evidentiary prin-
ciple that allowed evidence to be admitted regardless of how it was
obtained.
147
In light of this understanding of contemporary doctrine,
Boyd, Weeks, and Mapp are at best judicially creative and at worst,
terrible judge-made policy. Few, if any, scholars have studied how
these cases may have resulted from the dynamics created by
employing common law principles to enforce constitutional values.
The result is a general understanding that the exclusionary rule was a
remedy devised haphazardly by judges interested in preserving the
Fourth Amendment’s policies. As one scholar put it, the exclusionary
rule “is the product of a series of decisions by the United States
Supreme Court which may be traced back to Boyd v. United
143
See, e.g., Amar, Fourth Amendment, supra note 130, at 787 (“The confusion began
with the Supreme Court’s landmark 1886 case, Boyd v. United States.”); Barnett, supra
note 139, at 938 n.2 (characterizing the exclusionary rule as a “court-created rule,” devised
in Boyd and Weeks); Audrey S. Brent, Illegally Obtained Evidence: An Historical and
Comparative Analysis, 48 S
ASK
. L. R
EV
. 1, 20 (1984) (calling Weeks a “landmark judg-
ment” in “a new era of judicial interpretation”); Thomas Y. Davies, Recovering the
Original Fourth Amendment, 98 M
ICH
. L. R
EV
. 547, 556 (1999) (beginning the narrative of
the exclusionary rule with Weeks); Roots, supra note 138, at 1 (“The Fourth Amendment
exclusionary rule has been the law of the land in all federal jurisdictions since 1914 and in
all state jurisdictions since 1961.”); Lyle Denniston, Argument Preview: Police and
Changing Law, SCOTUS
BLOG
(Mar. 18, 2011, 3:42 PM), http://www.scotusblog.com/2011/
03/argument-preview-police-and-changing-law/ (“[The exclusionary rule] began[ ] in the
1914 case of Weeks v. U.S. . . . .”).
144
116 U.S. 616 (1886).
145
232 U.S. 383 (1914).
146
367 U.S. 643 (1961).
147
See, e.g., Commonwealth v. Dana, 43 Mass. (2 Met.) 329, 337 (1841).
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 36 21-MAR-12 13:28
April 2012] THE PATH OF THE CONSTITUTION 167
States.”
148
Akhil Amar, for example, criticizes the exclusionary rule as
a “concocted[,] . . . awkward and embarrassing remedy”
149
that is
essentially divorced from the “text, history, or structure of the Fourth
Amendment.”
150
In his view, “the Amendment presupposes a civil
damage remedy, not exclusion of evidence in criminal trials.”
151
Amar’s perspective actually goes further than most in understanding
the relationship between the Constitution and the common law, but
artificially limits the nexus to civil damage remedies. The principal
contention of this Article is that a more comprehensive understanding
of that relationship yields a more nuanced understanding of how the
exclusionary rule came to be.
That story begins with a simple but frequently overstated prin-
ciple of evidence law: The method by which evidence is acquired does
not, as a matter of evidence law, affect its competency to be presented
in a criminal trial. This principle is iterated in state and federal court
opinions
152
and reiterated by leading evidence treatises.
153
148
Jerry E. Norton, The Exclusionary Rule Reconsidered: Restoring the Status Quo
Ante, 33 W
AKE
F
OREST
L. R
EV
. 261, 263 (1998).
149
Amar, Fourth Amendment, supra note 130, at 785.
150
A
KHIL
R
EED
A
MAR
, T
HE
C
ONSTITUTION AND
C
RIMINAL
P
ROCEDURE
: F
IRST
P
RINCIPLES
91 (1997).
151
Amar, Fourth Amendment, supra note 130, at 758; cf. William J. Stuntz, Warrants
and Fourth Amendment Remedies, 77 V
A
. L. R
EV
. 881, 899 (1991) (“Before 1961 damages
were, in many states, the only sanction imposed for illegal searches and seizures.”).
152
For example, in Commonwealth v. Dana, the court reasoned that:
Admitting that the lottery tickets and materials were illegally seized, still this is
no legal objection to the admission of them in evidence. If the search warrant
were illegal, or if the officer serving the warrant exceeded his authority, the
party on whose complaint the warrant issued, or the officer, would be respon-
sible for the wrong done; but this is no good reason for excluding the papers
seized as evidence, if they were pertinent to the issue, as they unquestionably
were. When papers are offered in evidence, the court can take no notice how
they were obtained, whether lawfully or unlawfully; nor would they form a
collateral issue to determine that question.
43 Mass. (2 Met.) 329, 337 (1841) (emphases added). In People v. Adams, the court
explained: “The underlying principle obviously is that the court, when engaged in trying a
criminal cause, will not take notice of the manner in which witnesses have possessed them-
selves of papers or other articles of personal property which are material and properly
offered in evidence.” 68 N.E. 637, 638 (N.Y. 1903). The court in United States v. La Jeune
Eugenie, also reasoned similarly:
In the ordinary administration of municipal law the right of using evidence
does not depend . . . upon the lawfulness or unlawfulness of the mode, by
which it is obtained. If it is competent or pertinent evidence, and not in its own
nature objectionable, as having been created by constraint, or oppression, such
as confessions extorted by threats or fraud, the evidence is admissible on
charges for the highest crimes, even though it may have been obtained by a
trespass upon the person, or by any other forcible and illegal means. . . . In
many instances, and especially on trials for crimes, evidence is often obtained
from the possession of the offender by force or by contrivances, which one
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 37 21-MAR-12 13:28
168 NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:132
Scholars have interpreted this principle as a rejection of the
exclusionary rule. Boyd and Weeks are seen as departures, partly
because the evidentiary principle seemed to reject exclusion so clearly
as an appropriate remedy. As Justice Story observed:
In the ordinary administration of municipal law the right of using
evidence does not depend, nor, as far as I have any recollection, has
ever been supposed to depend upon the lawfulness or unlawfulness
of the mode, by which it is obtained. . . . I am not aware, that such
evidence has upon that account ever been dismissed for
incompetency.
154
But this is not, in fact, a principle that rejected exclusion in general.
Rather, it was just a principle of evidence law. At trial, a defendant
could not raise an evidentiary objection to evidence based on the
legality of its acquisition, unless the evidence was created or acquired
by threat or fraud.
155
In other words, if officers illegally snuck into
every home in a neighborhood until they discovered a bloody dagger,
and then turned that dagger over to the local prosecutor, they would
be guilty of multiple trespasses. But evidence law would not be
employed to bar admission of the murder weapon in a prosecution
against its possessor.
Boyd and Weeks effectively excluded evidence without disturbing
this principle. The facts of these cases are critical. In Boyd, the district
attorney brought a charge against the defendant for forfeiture of
property. Then, at trial, “it became important to show the quantity
and value of the glass contained in twenty-nine cases previously
imported,” so the court then ordered the defendant, over his constitu-
tional objections, “to produce the invoice of the twenty-nine cases.”
156
The issue was whether the court could invoke a statute to order a
defendant to produce self-incriminating evidence at trial. And the res-
olution of such a question, as Justice Bradley reasoned, turned on
both the Fourth Amendment right against unreasonable searches and
seizures and the Fifth Amendment right against self incrimination.
157
There are two critical distinctions necessary to understanding
Boyd. First, it is not uncommon to understand the entire criminal
could not easily reconcile to a delicate sense of propriety, or support upon the
foundations of municipal law. Yet I am not aware, that such evidence has upon
that account ever been dismissed for incompetency.
26 F. Cas. 832, 843–44 (C.C.D. Mass. 1822).
153
See, e.g., 1 S
IMON
G
REENLEAF
, A T
REATISE ON THE
L
AW O F
E
VIDENCE
§ 254a
(Simon Greenleaf Croswell ed., 14th rev’d ed. 1883).
154
La Jeune Eugenie, 26 F. Cas. at 843–44.
155
See, e.g., Dana, 43 Mass. (2 Met.) at 337–38.
156
Boyd v. United States, 116 U.S. 616, 618 (1886).
157
Id. at 633–34.
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 38 21-MAR-12 13:28
April 2012] THE PATH OF THE CONSTITUTION 169
process—from investigation to arrest to jail—as a single process car-
ried out by the state. But this is not entirely accurate. Traditionally,
when an officer seized evidence, the legality of that seizure was con-
sidered a matter separate and independent from the criminal trial
where evidence would be employed.
158
If the officer violated the
Fourth Amendment to seize that evidence, he did so personally,
because the federal government cannot cloak him with authority to
violate the Constitution as an officer of the government. By contrast, a
trial is something that the government is authorized to conduct. This is
where the evidentiary principle would kick in: At trial, courts would
not inquire into whether evidence was lawfully obtained. If a police
officer acted unlawfully, that would be a collateral issue resolved by a
separate lawsuit against the officer, not by an objection to the compe-
tence of evidence. Similarly, criminal trials would not pause to adjudi-
cate whether the police officer used unreasonable force in making the
arrest.
In Boyd, this was not the case because it was not an officer but
the district court, in the course of trying the defendant for forfeiture,
that ordered the evidence to be produced as part of that trial.
159
The
defendant immediately made a constitutional objection to this order.
Thus, the defendant was not objecting to evidence as a proxy for chal-
lenging the lawfulness of a police officer’s prior actions. He was in fact
contemporaneously objecting to an order by the trial court. This did
not require the court to stop and assess the collateral matter of
whether a police officer had, in the past, personally wronged the
defendant. Rather, the court was asked to consider the legality of its
own order. The court erred in rejecting the objection, and the appro-
priate remedy was a retrial, with the evidence returned to the defen-
dant and excluded because the district court could not lawfully order
its production.
160
The district court was not allowed, during the defen-
dant’s trial, to order him to produce papers, when such an order vio-
lated his Fourth and Fifth Amendment rights. This was seen as
significantly different from stopping a criminal trial to decide the
158
That is why courts often denied exclusion on the grounds that it was a collateral
matter not appropriately before the court during the criminal trial. See, e.g., Dana, 43
Mass. (2 Met.) at 337 (“When papers are offered in evidence, the court can take no notice
how they were obtained, whether lawfully or unlawfully; nor would they form a collateral
issue to determine that question.” (emphasis added)).
159
Of course, this order was carried out by an officer, but the key point is that because
this was part of the forfeiture trial, it was not a collateral issue requiring separate
adjudication.
160
Cf. Adams v. New York, 192 U.S. 585, 594 (1904) (finding no Fourth Amendment
error where the defendant did not object to a supposedly illegal seizure until witnesses
began testifying, despite having notice of the seizure).
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 39 21-MAR-12 13:28
170 NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:132
separate, civil matter of whether the officer seeking to introduce the
evidence was a lawful possessor of the evidence in the first place.
This leads to a second critical distinction: The invoices demanded
by the court in Boyd were in the rightful possession of the defen-
dant.
161
This is important in understanding how the relevant doctrines
intersected. That the invoices were lawfully possessed by the defen-
dant was essentially irrelevant to whether the search was a Fourth
Amendment violation per se, but not irrelevant to the question of
remedy.
162
Had the defendant lacked rightful possession of the prop-
erty—for example, if the property were stolen—he would not necessa-
rily be able to demand its return, because the relevant causes of action
might require the plaintiff to show that he had rightful possession of
the seized items. If the goods were stolen, his remedy would not be
return of the goods, but recovery in damages, assuming an unautho-
rized trespass,
163
and exclusion insofar as there was a Fifth
Amendment violation.
164
This second distinction helps shed light on Weeks v. United
States,
165
a case commonly, understandably, but erroneously cited as
fashioning a novel exclusionary rule for federal criminal trials.
166
The
case, decided by a unanimous Court, did something far less. There, the
defendant was arrested at his workplace while other officers raided his
home without warrant, taking “possession of various papers and arti-
cles found there.”
167
Before the trial, the defendant filed a petition
161
116 U.S. at 622–23.
162
It was also relevant to the Fifth Amendment right. Id. at 633 (“And we have been
unable to perceive that the seizure of a man’s private books and papers to be used in
evidence against him is substantially different from compelling him to be a witness against
himself.”).
163
As the Court pointed out in Boyd, the common law recognized many instances in
which seizure of a stolen or counterfeited good was not unreasonable. 116 U.S. at 623–24.
This only meant, however, that the primary constitutional question turned on whether
there was an unreasonable search or seizure, as the Fourth Amendment required.
164
It is worth clarifying the role of the Fifth Amendment here. There are two kinds of
self incrimination for purposes of that Amendment. The first is requiring the defendant to
take the stand, in response to which an objection at trial is appropriate. That evidence is
immediately excluded; if it is not, the defendant has grounds on which to seek a mistrial.
The second is unreasonably seizing the defendant’s property as evidence against him.
Because that approach turns on a Fourth Amendment question, it is incumbent upon the
defendant to petition for return of his property—that is, to seek a Fourth Amendment
remedy, first. He could not raise a Fifth Amendment issue during the criminal trial without
first seeking the Fourth Amendment remedy. Otherwise he would be collaterally attacking
the competency of evidence with an issue not relevant to the criminal trial itself.
165
232 U.S. 383 (1914), overruled by Mapp v. Ohio, 367 U.S. 643 (1961).
166
See Wolf v. Colorado, 338 U.S. 25, 28 (1949) (characterizing the exclusionary rule as
having been “made for the first time in 1914”), overruled by Mapp v. Ohio, 367 U.S. 643
(1961).
167
Weeks, 232 U.S. at 386.
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 40 21-MAR-12 13:28
April 2012] THE PATH OF THE CONSTITUTION 171
demanding return of his “[p]rivate [p]apers, [b]ooks, and [o]ther
[p]roperty.”
168
The district court ordered “the return of such property
as was not pertinent to the charge against the defendant,” but denied
the petition insofar as the property was pertinent to trial.
169
As a pre-
view of why the Supreme Court reversed this decision, we should ask
a tricky enumeration question: If the property belonged to the defen-
dant, and it was obtained by the officers in violation of the Fourth
Amendment, then how could the district court authorize the govern-
ment to retain possession of the defendant’s property when he
became a plaintiff properly filing for its return? In other words, how
did the government obtain a license to keep his property for the dura-
tion of the trial?
In addressing the Fourth Amendment claim, the unanimous
Court stressed that this case was not about “testimony offered at a
trial where the court is asked to stop and consider the illegal means by
which proofs, otherwise competent, were obtained.”
170
The case was
about whether the court could “retain for the purposes of evidence”
an accused individual’s property when that individual “without
awaiting his trial, made timely application to the court for an order for
the return of . . . [his] property.”
171
This is a property question: How is
the government keeping possession of the property? Does the govern-
ment have a license to keep any property it obtains for at least the
duration of a trial if that property was unlawfully obtained?
In answering these questions, the Court found that the eviden-
tiary principle—that “a court will not, in trying a criminal cause,
permit a collateral issue to be raised as to the source of competent
testimony”—was inapplicable in cases where the accused “applied . . .
in due season for the return of papers seized in violation of the
[Constitution].”
172
This is because a rule of evidence could not confer
a property right, in the form of a temporary license, to government
officials who were holding property unreasonably seized. The prop-
erty had to be returned as a matter of property law, even though it
would not be excluded as a matter of evidence law. The only limita-
tion is that a defendant could not raise a property claim in the middle
of a criminal trial, notwithstanding the strong nexus between the prop-
erty right and the criminal proceeding; he had to apply in “due
season[,]”
173
“without awaiting his trial.”
174
168
Id. at 387.
169
Id. at 388.
170
Id. at 392.
171
Id. at 393 (emphasis added).
172
Id. at 396.
173
Id. at 393.
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 41 21-MAR-12 13:28
172 NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:132
At this point, the narrowness of the evidentiary principle in fed-
eral court should be abundantly clear. As long as the property
belonged to the defendant and was seized illegally, he could have it
back through timely petition, in effect excluding it as evidence. In
other words, the evidentiary principle did not deprive the accused of
his common law causes of action. As discussed earlier, all actions
taken against the accused on the basis of an illegal search were
without defense, and thus unable to authorize any injuries those
actions imposed on the accused. Any such action could constitute
assault, battery, false imprisonment, false arrest, trespass, or any other
number of common law causes of action. The evidentiary principle did
not change this. Thus, if the remedy for unlawfully acquired property
included return of that property, the evidentiary principle had nothing
to say. It did not confer authority to hold the property, nor did it oth-
erwise purport to limit any rights.
This is not how we understand the modern exclusionary rule.
Weeks no doubt implicated Fourth Amendment policies about
securing one’s person and property from seizures, but these policies
were, at their core, driven by principles (and thus remedies) of prop-
erty law. The background principle is a combination of property law
and the enumeration principle: If an officer, pursuant to no legal
authority, seizes private property, the rightful owner could sue to
recover his property. This, by its own terms, implied two scenarios
where exclusion would not be available: (1) the plaintiff could not sue
to recover property for which she could not demonstrate title (for
example, stolen property),
175
and (2) the plaintiff could not sue to
recover any property seized pursuant to valid authority.
176
In addition to these, there was the evidentiary principle that crim-
inal trials would not be halted for collateral issues regarding the
source of otherwise competent evidence. Weeks did not adopt an
exclusionary rule, but reasserted a common law property remedy. In
other words, it resolved a question that foiled the tension between
174
Id. at 396.
175
Indeed, the defendant in Weeks emphasized in his brief that the property rightfully
belonged to him. See Statement, Specification of Errors and Brief for the Plaintiff in Error
at 4, Weeks, 232 U.S. 383 (1914) (No. 461).
176
Cf. United States v. Mills, 185 F. 318 (S.D.N.Y. 1911). In Mills, the court stated:
From time immemorial an officer making a lawful arrest on a criminal charge
has taken into his possession the instruments of the crime and such other arti-
cles as may reasonably be of use as evidence on the trial. A blood-stained knife
or garment, a half-emptied phial of poison, a mask or disguise, counterfeit
coins, plates for printing counterfeit notes, gambling devices, stolen property,
and many other articles are thus seized every day on the person or the prem-
ises of the alleged criminal, and no one disputes the propriety of such seizure.
Id. at 319 (emphasis added).
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 42 21-MAR-12 13:28
April 2012] THE PATH OF THE CONSTITUTION 173
property law and criminal evidence law: What if the accused moved to
recover his property before the trial began? This question was
answered in Weeks by the presumption of innocence, the concern
about self-incrimination,
177
and the primacy of property rights.
The evidentiary exclusionary rule evolved in this doctrinal thicket
from a property-based remedy to a truly evidentiary remedy, the one
we recognize today. The first step came in Silverthorne Lumber Co. v.
United States,
178
in which officers had seized papers, made copies, and
returned the originals upon district court order. After all this, how-
ever, the court subpoenaed the originals based on evidence gathered
from the copies made in the illegal seizure and then held the defen-
dants in contempt for failure to abide.
179
The problem, of course, was
that this did in two steps what the government could not do in one.
Rather than unreasonably seizing evidence, the government would
unreasonably seize it, document it, return it, and then coerce the
accused to hand it over on the basis of the unreasonable search and
seizure. Accordingly, Justice Holmes’s terse opinion took sweeping
language, rejecting the idea “that the protection of the Constitution
covers the physical possession but not any advantages that the
Government can gain over the object of its pursuit by doing the for-
bidden act.”
180
Critical here is that in Silverthorne, like in Boyd, the accused
objected to the court’s action—holding the accused in contempt for
failure to comply with an unauthorized subpoena—and, like in Boyd,
the property in question belonged to the accused. It was not an
attempt to stop the criminal trial to inquire into the unauthorized
actions of a police officer. Consequently, this did not implicate the
traditional rule of evidence that trials will not be stopped to determine
collateral issues, because the validity of the court’s contempt holding
turned on whether the court could use illegally obtained evidence as
the basis for coercing the production of that same evidence.
181
It could
not.
177
It is worth noting again the intimate relationship between the Fourth and Fifth
Amendment rights. The perception in these cases is that a court treads on the accused’s
Fifth Amendment right against self-incrimination when it violates the Fourth Amendment
to coerce the accused into licensing his property to the state for purposes of incriminating
himself. The contours of this interaction are interesting and are worth exploring elsewhere
but, for purposes of this Article, it is sufficient to highlight this relationship and note that it
played some role in conceptualizing the defendant’s experience with the criminal justice
system.
178
251 U.S. 385 (1920).
179
Id. at 391.
180
Id.
181
Justice Holmes’s opinion was to this effect. He rejected the idea that an unwarranted
seizure could become warranted by using “two steps . . . instead of one” (here, seizing the
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 43 21-MAR-12 13:28
174 NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:132
In Gouled v. United States,
182
an officer surreptitiously seized evi-
dence, a fact unbeknownst to the defendant until the evidence was
introduced at trial. Only then did the defendant object. The Court
held that “[t]he objection was not too late, for, coming as it did
promptly upon the first notice the defendant had that the
Government was in possession of the paper, the rule of practice relied
upon, that such an objection will not be entertained unless made
before trial, was obviously inapplicable.”
183
In another case that same
term, the Court found that a petition for return of property was not
“too late when presented after the jury was empaneled,” and thus the
subsequent motion to exclude could not be denied “by the rule that in
the progress of the trial of criminal cases courts will not stop to frame
a collateral issue to inquire whether evidence offered, otherwise com-
petent, was lawfully or unlawfully obtained.”
184
These cases more intimately tie property rights with Fourth
Amendment rights, the implication being that the remedy afforded by
property law was servicing both rights. Specifically, in Amos, the
Court allowed the defendant to apply for his property even after the
jury was empaneled because he did not have a fair chance to do so
before that point. This inquiry—whether the defendant had a fair
chance to ask for his property back—is not part of “property” law.
Rather, it signals that the Court abandoned the fiction that the prop-
erty right violated by the officer was wholly separate from the criminal
prosecution and increasingly understood the two as related. As a
result, the Court became increasingly willing to adjudicate “property”
issues in the context of criminal trials.
More difficult were trials involving drug possession, where the
accused (if guilty) possessed property she had no legal right to pos-
sess. This presented an awkward tension between the presumption of
innocence and the unpalatable remedy of returning illegal drugs to a
drug dealer or consumer. The Court artfully resolved this issue in
Agnello v. United States, in which the government had illegally seized
cocaine from the defendant’s home that the defendant denied ever
having.
185
The Court held that the evidence was inadmissible, bor-
rowing its primary rationale from Boyd: Introduction of illegally
seized evidence violates not only the Fourth Amendment right, but
also the Fifth Amendment right against self-incrimination. As a result,
papers, copying them, and basing a legal order on the latter, as opposed to merely seizing
them). Id.
182
255 U.S. 298 (1921).
183
Id. at 305.
184
Amos v. United States, 255 U.S. 313, 316 (1921).
185
Agnello v. United States, 269 U.S. 20, 29–30 (1925).
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 44 21-MAR-12 13:28
April 2012] THE PATH OF THE CONSTITUTION 175
the Court held that “there is no reason why one whose rights have
been so violated and who is sought to be incriminated by evidence so
obtained, may not invoke protection of the Fifth Amendment immedi-
ately and without any application for the return of the thing
seized.”
186
Of course, the government argued that there was a reason,
and a good reason at that: the evidentiary principle that stood against
halting a criminal trial to adjudicate whether evidence should be
excluded on the basis of how it was obtained. As the government
argued, “even if the search and seizure were unlawful, the evidence
was admissible because no application on behalf of defendant was
made to the court for the return of the can of cocaine.”
187
The Court disagreed for two reasons. First, because the defendant
was insisting upon his innocence, “[i]t would be unreasonable to hold
that he was bound to apply for the return of an article which he main-
tained he never had.”
188
What makes the difference here is the Fifth
Amendment. If the Court ruled against the defendant, the govern-
ment would have the benefit of an unconstitutional checkmate: The
defendant would be forced either to incriminate himself by applying
for the drug’s return, or sit on his Fourth Amendment right against
unreasonable searches by allowing the prosecutor to use the drugs as
evidence. This rationale—which allows the accused to assert a prop-
erty law remedy while denying an actual property right in the item—
underscores that the remedy afforded by property law was by now (if
not all along) well understood as a remedy for the Fourth Amendment
right. This is not entirely surprising, as the Fourth Amendment pro-
tects property (among other things) by securing it from unreasonable
invasion.
Second, there was no evidence to suggest that the accused “knew
that the government claimed it had searched his house and found
cocaine there, or that the prosecutor intended to introduce evidence
of any search or seizure.”
189
This pushed the Court’s jurisprudence
with regard to timing to its logical conclusion, which is that the defen-
dant must file for return of his property, as the government suggests,
but is not expected to do so insofar as he is not aware that his property
was taken. The evidentiary principle was thus dismissed as a “rule of
practice [that] . . . must not be allowed . . . to prevail over a constitu-
tional right.”
190
186
Id. at 34.
187
Id.
188
Id.
189
Id.
190
Id. at 34–35 (quoting Gouled v. United States, 255 U.S. 298, 313 (1921)).
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 45 21-MAR-12 13:28
176 NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:132
2. Incorporating the Federal Exclusionary Rule
As we have seen, the federal exclusionary rule—a principle of
evidence in criminal trials—derived essentially from the remedies
available for violations of civil property law. But exclusion was not
merely the exercise of a civil property right. As we saw, when the
defendant had sued or moved to recover his property, the question
was whether the government has a right to hold on to that property.
When the answer was no, it was because doing so violated the defen-
dant’s Fourth Amendment right—that is, the guarantee that he is
secure in his person, houses, papers, and effects against unreasonable
searches and seizures. This right protected property from unreason-
able searches and seizures, but nothing more or less.
191
In the seminal 1961 case Mapp v. Ohio, the Supreme Court incor-
porated the exclusionary rule against the states. The decision in Mapp
has been commended,
192
criticized,
193
extended,
194
and, more recently,
contracted.
195
But incorporating the right against unreasonable
searches and seizures was not as simple as it may now seem. Once
incorporated, remedies for Fourth Amendment violations would
hinge on a state’s configuration of its property law, creating concerns
about variation in the right’s robustness from state to state. The ques-
tion would be whether the Fourth Amendment right, once incorpo-
rated, would bring with it its property remedy, or whether that right
would depend on each state’s property law. The story of Mapp is the
story of how the Court dealt with these concerns. It is, by extension,
191
Of course, other property rights are protected elsewhere in the Constitution, for
example by the Takings Clause and by the Due Process Clause more generally.
192
Potter Stewart, The Road to Mapp v. Ohio and Beyond: The Origins, Development
and Future of the Exclusionary Rule in Search-and-Seizure Cases, 83 C
OLUM
. L. R
EV
. 1365,
1389 (1983) (“[T]he exclusionary rule is constitutionally required, not as a ‘right’ explicitly
incorporated in the fourth amendment’s prohibitions, but as a remedy necessary to ensure
that those prohibitions are observed in fact.” (emphasis omitted)).
193
See, e.g., Stone v. Powell, 428 U.S. 465, 498 (1976) (“A more clumsy, less direct
means of imposing sanctions is difficult to imagine . . . .”).
194
See, e.g., Wong Sun v. United States, 371 U.S. 471, 485 (1963) (excluding presenta-
tion of verbal evidence and recovered narcotics where they were both fruits of an illegal
entry).
195
See, e.g., Davis v. United States, 131 S. Ct. 2419, 2429 (2011) (holding that searches
conducted in objectively reasonable reliance on binding appellate precedent are not sub-
ject to the exclusionary rule); INS v. Lopez-Mendoza, 468 U.S. 1032, 1042 (1984) (not
applying the exclusionary rule to deportation proceedings because “social costs” exceed
“deterrence value”); United States v. Havens, 446 U.S. 620, 627–28 (1980) (holding that
the exclusionary rule does not bar evidence from being used to impeach a defendant’s
testimony); Rakas v. Illinois, 439 U.S. 128, 134 (1978) (holding that a passenger does not
have standing to object to search of vehicle); see also The Supreme Court, 2005 Term—
Leading Cases, 120 H
ARV
. L. R
EV
. 125, 183 (2006) (“It remains to be seen how far the
Court will go, but Hudson is a strong signal that the exclusionary rule is in trouble.”).
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 46 21-MAR-12 13:28
April 2012] THE PATH OF THE CONSTITUTION 177
the story of how the Court dealt with the relationship between the
Constitution and a diverging common law.
The story begins with Wolf v. Colorado, in which the Court held
that the Fourteenth Amendment incorporated the right against unrea-
sonable searches and seizures, but did not compel the exclusionary
rule.
196
Justice Frankfurter’s opinion for the 6-3 majority began with
the premise that the exclusionary rule was an evidentiary device
“made for the first time in [Weeks in] 1914.”
197
As we have seen, this
is an overstatement, predicated on employing the term “exclusionary
rule” to conflate a variety of interconnecting doctrines.
Wolf incorporated the right against unreasonable searches and
seizures because it deemed such a right to be “implicit in ‘the concept
of ordered liberty,’” thus meeting the standard by which the Due
Process Clause incorporates rights against the states.
198
The same
standard allowed the Court to deny mandating a particular remedy:
“We cannot . . . regard it as a departure from basic standards to
remand . . . [those illegally searched] to the remedies of private action
and such protection as the internal discipline of the police . . . may
afford.”
199
This position was practically and logically problematic, given the
development of the Fourth Amendment in the federal context. Justice
Murphy’s dissent recounts some of the pragmatic problems with
claiming that injured parties have other remedies
200
—many of which
should be familiar after the discussion above. To reiterate, however,
this decision took place against a backdrop of growing doctrines of
officer immunity found in state law, as well as the declining practi-
cality of actually suing officers for trespass. Thus, those “remedies of
private action” that the majority relied upon were in the process of
dwindling.
Moreover, the logic of incorporating the Fourth Amendment but
not the exclusionary rule was in tension with the enumeration prin-
ciple, as now the same powers not conferred to the federal govern-
ment were also withheld from state governments. If the state is not
196
338 U.S. 25, 28 (1949).
197
Id. at 28.
198
Id. at 27 (quoting Palko v. Connecticut, 302 U.S. 319, 325 (1937)).
199
Id. at 31 (emphasis added).
200
These problems included the fact that damages were limited to injury incurred by
physical property, various states’ limitations or bars on punitive damages, the admissibility
of evidence of the plaintiff’s bad reputation, and the problem of states that made use of
evidence at trial a complete justification for the search. Finally, “even if the plaintiff hur-
dles all these obstacles, and gains a substantial verdict, the individual officer’s finances may
well make the judgment useless—for the municipality, of course, is not liable without its
consent.” Id. at 42–44 (Murphy, J., dissenting).
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 47 21-MAR-12 13:28
178 NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:132
given the power to conduct unreasonable searches and seizures, this
means, as noted earlier, that there is no cognizable authorization for
unreasonable searches or seizures that agents of the state could
invoke. It is unclear, then, how agents of the state could, consistent
with the Fourth Amendment, retain property unreasonably seized
when presented with a timely petition for a return of that property.
Their defense, if accepted, would necessarily grant the government
privileges with regards to goods unreasonably seized. Whether the
property is in the possession of a police officer or a clerk of the court,
somewhere an agent is holding the suspect’s property without authori-
zation (that is, license). In short, regardless of who ultimately has con-
trol of the property, that control would be traced to an unlawful
search and seizure that cannot legally convey such a license.
201
This
was the teaching of federal case law leading up to and following
Weeks. Absent this understanding, states could discriminate against
the Fourth Amendment right or vastly change the scope of that right
by tinkering with their common law, raising an interesting analogy to
the Court’s jurisprudence generally prohibiting states from discrimi-
nating against federal rights.
202
Wolf avoided this problem by incorporating the policy but not the
text or logic of the Fourth Amendment. Allowing damages but not
exclusion seemed to satisfy the policy that government should not
unlawfully search and seize evidence. But doing so created its own
problems. To the extent that the Court was concerned with policy, it
had to deal with the problem of declining common law remedies.
More fundamentally, Wolf implicitly welcomed litigants to bring suits
challenging the extent to which state remedies fulfilled Fourth
Amendment policy. The Court’s logic in declining to incorporate
exclusion was that while the Fourth Amendment right was implicit in
the concept of ordered liberty, exclusion was not. This invited chal-
lenges to various state remedies on the ground that the remedies
failed to protect sufficiently a right that was necessary to ordered lib-
201
The court in Hoyer v. State, alludes to this point:
To say, then, that when the state itself has thus violated its own pledges, it may
use the results thereby obtained for its own purpose, become a party to the
trespass by ratification, trace its title through wrongful acts of its officers,
remain itself immune, in its sovereignty, from legal liability, and then relegate
the individual whose rights are thus swept away and made valueless in and by a
court of justice, to his bootless and fruitless action of trespass against such
trespassing state officials as individuals, is to gibe and to jeer.
193 N.W. 89, 93 (Wis. 1923) (emphasis added).
202
See, e.g., Testa v. Katt, 330 U.S. 386, 389 (1947) (states may not discriminate against
federal rights); Haywood v. Drown, 129 S. Ct. 2108, 2115 (2009) (same, even if federal
rights are particularly costly).
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 48 21-MAR-12 13:28
April 2012] THE PATH OF THE CONSTITUTION 179
erty. In turn, the holding in Wolf, which was premised in part on con-
cerns about federalism, threatened vast and unprincipled federal
interference with state common law. Incorporating the Fourth
Amendment meant imposing a minimum level of protection for the
individual right, below which the states could not go. Otherwise, Wolf
would stand for nothing more than a Supreme Court statement
encouraging states to consider the Fourth Amendment. This created
the potential for a major jurisprudential problem: The Court would
now have to decide which common law features remedying unreason-
able searches and seizures—for example, officer immunities, punitive
damages, rules of evidence, the availability and robustness of common
law causes of action—were necessary to satisfy the Constitution.
Though the question of overruling Wolf was not briefed before
the Court in Mapp v. Ohio,
203
the majority opinion was motivated by
these very concerns. As Justice Douglas put it, “[t]he immediate result
[of the Court’s decision in Wolf] was a storm of constitutional contro-
versy which only today finds its end.”
204
Indeed, the Court had been
petitioned to overrule the Wolf decision “Term after Term,”
205
about
fifteen times per Term in the three years before Mapp.
206
The Court in Mapp began by citing precedent establishing that
the exclusionary rule was rooted in a specific, well-recognized consti-
tutional logic: that the essence of the offense was “not the breaking of
[one’s] doors, and the rummaging of his drawers,” but rather “the
invasion of [the defendant’s] indefeasible right of personal security,
personal liberty and private property” committed by holding his pri-
vate items “to be used as evidence to convict him of crime . . . .”
207
This indefeasible right meant that officers could not be authorized to
seize or to retain seized evidence, or any property for that matter,
208
if
203
367 U.S. 643, 646 n.3 (1961).
204
Id. at 670 (Douglas, J., concurring).
205
Id. at 654 (majority opinion).
206
Id. at 676 (Harlan, J., dissenting). Of course, Mapp did not actually overrule Wolf so
much as it extended it. Wolf, as mentioned earlier, only somewhat incorporated the Fourth
Amendment—its policies, but not its text or logic. Mapp went ahead with full incorpora-
tion and, in doing so, overruled Wolf only insofar as Mapp required exclusion.
207
Id. at 646–47 (quoting Boyd v. United States, 116 U.S. 616, 630 (1886)).
208
Note a very interesting point here: The remedy is derived from property law, but the
right is something broader than a property right. The Fourth Amendment guarantees
“[t]he right of the people to be secure in their persons, houses, papers, and effects, against
unreasonable searches and seizures.” U.S. C
ONST
. amend. IV. As we saw in Silverthorne
Lumber Co. v. United States, 251 U.S. 385, 391–92 (1920), the Court did not construe the
Fourth Amendment as merely a property right. See supra notes 178–81 and accompanying
text (discussing Silverthorne Lumber as the first step in the evolution of the exclusionary
rule from a property-based remedy to an evidentiary remedy). The government was not
allowed to document illegally acquired evidence as a means by which to authorize further
government action. This decision had consequences beyond what is guaranteed by a prop-
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 49 21-MAR-12 13:28
180 NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:132
the seizure was done pursuant to an unreasonable search. The Court
relied on Weeks to assert that the Fourth Amendment stood for, if
nothing else, the idea that private belongings could not “be seized and
held and used . . . against a citizen.”
209
The Constitution gives the
government power to retain such property only if that property was
obtained in a manner consistent with the Fourth Amendment. Thus,
by authorizing the officer to hold evidence that was obtained in viola-
tion of the Fourth Amendment, the government would be conferring
on him a legal privilege that the Fourth Amendment does not allow
the government to confer. In short, the government was exercising a
power it did not have. This contradicted the enumeration principle in
a fundamental and arguably irreconcilable way.
210
Consequently, even
Justice Black, not known for extra-textual enthusiasm, found that the
Constitution “not only justifies but actually requires the exclusionary
rule.”
211
Over and over, the Court repeated that the exclusionary rule
was not a rule of evidence but a constitutional rule that said that what
the Fourth Amendment forbade could not “find . . . sanction in the
judgments of the courts,” unless of course no timely petition was
filed.
212
This rule had implications for evidentiary law insofar as
officers or courts attempted to hold property seized in violation of the
Fourth Amendment, but it did not “refer[ ] to or limit[ ] the use of
evidence in courts.” This was a long way of saying that it was not a
right to exclusion, but an application of the enumeration principle in
the context of Fourth Amendment seizures, which, in turn, had a
“striking outcome” for evidence law.
213
Striking, but “logically and
erty right. For example, it then became arguable that if the government illegally seized
information, that information could not satisfy its burden of proof during a prosecution.
Put differently, the government could not take action that it would not have been able to
take but for the unlawfully seized evidence. This conclusion of course raises questions
about proximate cause, but also sheds light on modern intuitions such as the fruit of the
poisonous tree doctrine.
209
Mapp, 367 U.S. at 648 (quoting Weeks v. United States, 232 U.S. 383, 393 (1914))
(emphasis added).
210
Cf. id. at 660 (“The ignoble shortcut to conviction left open to the State tends to
destroy the entire system of constitutional restraints on which the liberties of the people
rest.”).
211
Id. at 662 (Black, J., concurring). Justice Black’s decision was impressed specifically
by the interaction between the Fourth and Fifth Amendments. As mentioned earlier, this
does not change the logic presented here that has assumed, like Boyd, the relationship
between the Fourth and Fifth Amendments.
212
Id. at 648–49 (majority opinion) (quoting Weeks, 232 U.S. at 392); see also id. at 670
(Douglas, J., concurring) (stating that Wolf eviscerated the Fourth Amendment by doing
exactly what it prohibited: “allow[ing] States to give constitutional sanction to the ‘shabby
business’ of unlawful entry into a home” (quoting Wolf v. Colorado, 338 U.S. 25, 46 (1948)
(Murphy, J., dissenting))).
213
Id. at 649 (quoting Olmstead v. United States, 277 U.S. 438, 462 (1928)).
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 50 21-MAR-12 13:28
April 2012] THE PATH OF THE CONSTITUTION 181
constitutionally necessary.”
214
The Court took this “logical dictate”
215
seriously,
216
as it downplayed the availability of other remedial
schemes as “not basically relevant.”
217
It is true that such alternatives
had no role to play in the logic of why the exclusionary rule was
required by the Fourth Amendment, but they were not exactly irrele-
vant. A broader historical canvas suggests that the problems with state
common law remedial systems actually pushed the Court to incorpo-
rate the Fourth Amendment more fully in the first place. The
majority’s dismissal of Wolf’s reasoning as “bottomed on factual con-
siderations”
218
was motivated not by ideology, but by deep jurispru-
dential concerns—both principled and pragmatic—about both how
the Constitution was to interact with local remedial systems and what
the Court’s role would be in overseeing that interaction.
219
Accepting
the Wolf rationale would have required the Court to constantly mon-
itor all fifty states to “consider the current validity of the factual
grounds upon which Wolf was based,”
220
mainly the availability of
adequate remedies. That would have been no easy task, and hardly
one sensitive to federalism. The Court noted the experience of states
that had found that “such other remedies [mentioned by the Court in
Wolf] have been worthless and futile.”
221
As Justice Douglas stated in
his concurrence, “[t]he truth is that trespass actions against officers
who make unlawful searches and seizures are mainly illusory reme-
dies.”
222
In sum, the Court in Mapp perceived three choices: (1)
Essentially unincorporate the Fourth Amendment by abandoning fed-
eral enforcement, thus leaving enforcement to dwindling state law
remedies, (2) monitor and inject federal standards into state common
law regimes, or (3) incorporate the logic of the exclusionary rule. The
entirety of the opinion is devoted to why it chose the third.
214
Id. at 656.
215
Id. at 657.
216
See id. at 659 (“Nothing can destroy a government more quickly than its failure to
observe its own laws, or worse, its disregard of the charter of its own existence.”).
217
Id. at 651.
218
Id.
219
See also id. at 666 (Black, J., concurring) (noting that the Court was “dissipat[ing] the
doubt and uncertainty in this field of constitutional law” by rejecting the “confusing” Wolf
doctrine in exchange for “the precise, intelligible and more predictable constitutional doc-
trine enunciated in the Boyd case”).
220
Id. at 651 (majority opinion).
221
Id. at 652.
222
Id. at 670 (Douglas, J., concurring).
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 51 21-MAR-12 13:28
182 NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:132
B. Federal Cause of Action
The relationship between the common law and the Constitution,
and the Court’s management of that relationship, implicated much
more than the application of the exclusionary rule. In the following
Sections, this Article uses the lens of common law remedies to under-
stand Monroe and Bivens. Once again common law remedies provide
an interesting and useful lens through which to examine how these
cases were shaped. The weakening of the common law remedies drew
attention to the difficulties of having constitutional rights rely on
them; in turn, this increased the salience of arguments that could
avoid these difficulties by, for example, providing some sort of
administrable remedy that would not grow or shrink at the whim of
state common law. Both of these cases were about preserving the path
of the Constitution in the face of an ever-differing route taken by the
common law.
1. Monroe v. Pape
The Civil Rights Act of 1871, more popularly known as § 1983,
establishes a tort-like remedy for persons deprived of federally pro-
tected rights “under color of any statute, ordinance, regulation,
custom, or usage.”
223
In Monroe v. Pape, the Court held that § 1983
provides a remedy to parties deprived of their federal rights “by an
official’s abuse of his position.”
224
In other words, an officer can be
acting “under color of” state law even if the officer’s conduct is wholly
unauthorized by state law.
225
To reach their conclusions, the majority
and the dissent both rely heavily on the legislative history of § 1983.
Scholars have done the same.
226
Indeed, even beyond the legislative
223
42 U.S.C. § 1983 (2006). In its entirety, § 1983 provides:
Every person who, under color of any statute, ordinance, regulation, custom,
or usage, of any State or Territory or the District of Columbia, subjects, or
causes to be subjected, any citizen of the United States or other person within
the jurisdiction thereof to the deprivation of any rights, privileges, or immuni-
ties secured by the Constitution and laws, shall be liable to the party injured in
an action at law, suit in equity, or other proper proceeding for redress, except
that in any action brought against a judicial officer for an act or omission taken
in such officer’s judicial capacity, injunctive relief shall not be granted unless a
declaratory decree was violated or declaratory relief was unavailable. For the
purposes of this section, any Act of Congress applicable exclusively to the
District of Columbia shall be considered to be a statute of the District of
Columbia.
224
Monroe v. Pape, 365 U.S. 167, 172 (1961).
225
Id. at 184.
226
See, e.g., J
OHN
C. J
EFFRIES
, J
R
.
ET AL
., C
IVIL
R
IGHTS
A
CTIONS
: E
NFORCING THE
C
ONSTITUTION
45 n.g (2007) (noting that scholars have reached “diametrically opposed
interpretations” of the history of § 1983).
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 52 21-MAR-12 13:28
April 2012] THE PATH OF THE CONSTITUTION 183
history, almost anything that can be said about Monroe has been said
in the nearly two thousand law review articles that cite the case. This
Article does not weigh in on whether Monroe was wise or sound.
Instead, it discusses Monroe in the context of common law remedies
in order to better understand its result.
It is no coincidence that Monroe v. Pape came on the heels of
growing problems with common law remedies. The majority opinion
first identifies three policies in § 1983: (1) to “override certain kinds of
state laws,” (2) to “provide a [federal] remedy where state law was
inadequate,” and (3) “to provide a federal remedy where the state
remedy, though adequate in theory, was not available in practice.”
227
As these policy goals imply, the Civil Rights Act was, at least in
theory, designed to interact with the system of common law remedies
existing in the states; it did so by introducing a federal remedy where
state remedies had failed.
228
Without the benefit of Monroe, a plaintiff
would seek recovery by filing a common law suit against the trans-
gressing officers (for trespass, false imprisonment, battery, or
whatever cause of action applied). Upon filing suit, one of two out-
comes was possible for a meritorious claim. First, the plaintiff could
win in state court and be fairly compensated for his injury. Second, the
plaintiff could be denied relief, either by an unfavorable verdict, at the
damages stage, or on appeal. This could happen because of bad faith,
good faith misapplication of constitutional law, or some other facet of
the common law remedy like officer immunity.
The first scenario, where the injured person is compensated, is a
happy one, at least as far as the judiciary is concerned. The second
provides the logic that drove Monroe. In this scenario, there is a plain-
tiff who was injured by an officer’s unconstitutional action, but who
loses in court because, for example, the state court misinterpreted the
Constitution or provided the officer with immunity for unconstitu-
tional conduct. In these circumstances, the courts are implicitly
authorizing the officer’s unconstitutional conduct by protecting him
against valid legal challenges.
229
There is no doubt that an officer acts
under color of law if he searches pursuant to a statute providing that
“officers may unreasonably search homes.” But a law declaring that
227
Monroe, 365 U.S. at 173–74.
228
The Act’s original title is particularly interesting: “An act to protect all persons in the
United States in their civil rights, and to furnish the means of their vindication.” Civil
Rights Act of 1871, 17 Stat. 13.
229
Cf. Weeks v. United States, 232 U.S. 383, 394 (1914) (“To sanction [unconstitutional
behavior] would be to affirm by judicial decision a manifest neglect if not an open defiance
of the prohibitions of the Constitution, intended for the protection of the people against
such unauthorized action.”).
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 53 21-MAR-12 13:28
184 NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:132
“officers may unreasonably search” is in effect no different than one
that declares that “there shall be no legal repercussions for unreason-
able searches conducted by officers.” Nor are any of these different
from a court-made doctrine providing officers with such immunity.
They each have the same effect as is relevant here: They establish a
legal privilege under which the officer may act. The same is true when
a state court misinterprets the Constitution to allow an officer to do
something that the Constitution actually prohibits. It creates a legal
regime in which an officer may act under the privilege of law, immune
from reproach or repercussion.
Put in the language of § 1983, officers act under color of law
when state courts authorize or immunize their conduct, or do anything
to provide that conduct with a “privileged” status. Accordingly, if a
plaintiff brought a meritorious claim against an officer and was denied
relief in state court, a § 1983 claim would ripen.
230
That is, after the
officer’s conduct is blessed by the state court, the officer, who
deprived the plaintiff of a constitutional right, can be described as
acting under color of state law. This means that after losing in state
court, the plaintiff can sue under § 1983, alleging that the officer
deprived him of a federal right under color of state law.
In the world before Monroe, the logic and operation of § 1983
promised a potentially long but ultimately successful path for merito-
rious claims. If a plaintiff had a meritorious claim, he would either
have his injury redressed in state court, or have a cause of action in
federal court under § 1983. And indeed, Justice Frankfurter, who dis-
sented in Monroe, concluded that “[a]ll the evidence converges to the
conclusion that Congress by § [1983] created a civil liability enforce-
able in the federal courts only in instances of injury for which redress
was barred in the state courts . . . .”
231
Under that view, the plaintiff
was relegated to the state tort system. If he lost on a meritorious con-
stitutional claim, however, then he had a “civil liability enforceable in
the federal courts.”
232
But the majority in Monroe rejected Justice Frankfurter’s vision
of the relationship between state courts, federal courts, and § 1983
230
Cf. Monroe, 365 U.S. at 242 (Frankfurter, J., dissenting) (arguing that “remed[ies]
devolve[ ], in the first instance, on the States,” but conceding that “[o]f course, if the States
afford less protection against the police, as police, than against the hoodlum—if under
authority of state ‘statute, ordinance, regulation, custom, or usage’ the police are specially
shielded,” then § 1983 would apply). Such jurisdiction would not be barred by estoppel
principles because the elements forming the claim had not yet occurred.
231
Id. at 237.
232
Id.
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 54 21-MAR-12 13:28
April 2012] THE PATH OF THE CONSTITUTION 185
without ever making its own view entirely clear. The most important
lines in the opinion read cryptically:
It is no answer that the State has a law which if enforced would give
relief. The federal remedy is supplementary to the state remedy,
and the latter need not be first sought and refused before the federal
one is invoked. Hence the fact that Illinois by its constitution and
laws outlaws unreasonable searches and seizures is no barrier to the
present suit in the federal court.
233
Monroe held that rather than going to state court first, plaintiffs could
simply procure the inevitable by filing a § 1983 action in federal court.
That is, Monroe provided a shortcut.
As an aside, this conclusion accords with the Court’s holding
decades earlier in Home Telephone & Telegraph Co. v. City of Los
Angeles.
234
There, the Court held that where a plaintiff was asserting a
Fourteenth Amendment due process claim and a state law claim, fed-
eral courts need not wait for state courts to adjudicate the state law
claim.
235
That case provides an interesting insight into the relationship
between federal and state law: An unconstitutional action can be nul-
lified by either state or federal law, and neither the state nor federal
question must be answered first. Thus, even if something is unlawful
under state law, and thus perhaps not “state action” in the formal
sense (because the state does not allow such action), it can still be
rendered null by federal law without waiting to see if state law nulli-
fies it first.
Similarly, in Monroe, the Court held that a person deprived of
her constitutional rights by an officer need not go to state court for
redress before filing in federal court.
236
The difference between Home
Telephone and Monroe, of course, is that in Monroe, the cause of
action arises from a statute that requires the officer to have been
acting under color of state law. The majority and Justice Frankfurter
agreed that an officer acts under color of state law if (1) he trespasses
or otherwise injures a plaintiff without having constitutional authority
to do so, and (2) the officer is not held liable just as any other
person—that is, non-officer person—would be liable for committing
the same act (be it trespass, theft, etc.).
237
In other words, if state
233
Id. at 183 (emphasis added).
234
227 U.S. 278 (1913).
235
Id. at 283–84.
236
Monroe, 365 U.S. at 183.
237
Id. at 242 (Frankfurter, J., dissenting) (“Of course, if the States afford less protection
against the police, as police, than against the hoodlum—if under authority of state ‘statute,
ordinance, regulation, custom, or usage’ the police are specially shielded— 1983] pro-
vides a remedy which dismissal of petitioners’ complaint in the present case does not
impair.”).
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 55 21-MAR-12 13:28
186 NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:132
courts denied relief against officers who acted unconstitutionally,
those officers were acting under color of state law. The majority and
Justice Frankfurter parted ways, however, in that the majority was
willing to provide a shortcut: Rather than wait for the state court to
deny relief first, the plaintiff could just sue in federal court.
But this characterization of Monroe as a shortcut to the inevi-
table is misleading in an important way. To be sure, if a plaintiff has a
meritorious constitutional claim against an officer, and the state court
denies relief, then the officer can be seen as acting under color of state
law. But what if the state court does not (or was not going to) deny
relief? Monroe allows a federal remedy nonetheless. Thus, Monroe is
only a “shortcut” insofar as the state court was going to deny ade-
quate relief; otherwise, it is a supplement to the state law remedy.
This result is in part attributable to the difficult question of what
relief a state must provide so that it does not legally privilege an
officer’s unconstitutional conduct. The logic of § 1983 was, in part,
premised on the general availability of state forums to adjudicate the
rights within § 1983’s ambit and to provide adequate relief. In theory,
courts should punish the officer as though he was not an officer but an
ordinary person violating another person’s common law rights. Just as
in Little v. Barreme, the fact that the officer thought he was doing his
job or even following instructions “cannot change the nature of the
transaction, or legalize an act which without those instructions would
have been [unlawful].”
238
But, of course, in the decades prior to
Monroe, the common law remedies relied upon in § 1983’s logic
drifted, fragmented, contracted, and ultimately withered as practical
options for relief.
Monroe avoided that problem by passing over state courts alto-
gether. Plaintiffs could seek remedy in federal court, and federal
courts could provide this remedy without having to inquire into the
adequacy of state law remedies. Thus, the fact that Monroe came
when it did should not be too surprising. Monroe, decided the same
term as Mapp, was motivated by the same concerns about federalism
and judicial administration, and arose from the same problem of
diminished common law remedies. If the rights were systematically
withering, the alternative seemed an empty formality: Plaintiffs would
have to parade through the state system as a formalistic prerequisite
to obtaining a ripened § 1983 claim, and even if they were afforded
238
6 U.S. (2 Cranch) 170, 179 (1804).
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 56 21-MAR-12 13:28
April 2012] THE PATH OF THE CONSTITUTION 187
relief in state court, there would be difficult questions about whether
the relief was sufficient.
239
This was not just an empty formalism and a waste of time and
state resources. It was also offensive to federalism, as federal courts
would essentially be sitting as courts of constitutional error correction
for civil claims in state courts.
240
Justice Harlan reiterated this point in
his concurrence, where he noted that interpreting § 1983 otherwise
would “reduce the statute to having merely a jurisdictional function,
shifting the load of federal supervision from the Supreme Court to the
lower courts and providing a federal tribunal for fact findings in cases
involving authorized action.”
241
Federal courts would have to decide
whether state common law practices—including their procedural cir-
cumstances, provisions of immunity, and approaches to damages—
were interfering with the vindication of federal rights. Monroe
decided that the intent of § 1983 was to provide a simpler and less
intrusive process: sidestep the state courts, and file in federal court.
It is also worth pausing to consider the timing of Monroe. As one
commentator noted, there were only twenty-one suits under § 1983
between 1871 and 1920.
242
Members of the Court and other commen-
tators have interpreted this fact as suggesting that before Monroe,
§ 1983 was a more humble statute that was interpreted narrowly by
courts.
243
The implication is that § 1983 was not intended to be a
239
Justice Frankfurter seemed to agree with this logic in theory, but remained factually
unpersuaded that the common law remedies for suing officers were more limited than
those for suing an “individual hoodlum intruder.” Monroe, 365 U.S. at 242. Justice
Frankfurter goes on to say: “Of course, if the States afford less protection against the
police, as police, than against the hoodlum—if under authority of state ‘statute, ordinance,
regulation, custom, or usage’ the police are specially shielded—[§ 1983] provides a remedy
which dismissal of petitioners’ complaint in the present case does not impair.” Id. at
242–43.
240
That the writ of certiorari is discretionary only adds to this concern. This also calls to
mind James Madison’s concerns leading up to the Madisonian Compromise. In response to
proposals that federal courts sit as appellate courts over state tribunals, Madison expressed
unease regarding the magnitude of work this would create for federal courts. See 1 T
HE
R
ECORDS OF THE
F
EDERAL
C
ONVENTION OF
1787, at 124 (Max Farrand ed., 1911).
241
Monroe, 365 U.S. at 195.
242
Comment, The Civil Rights Act: Emergence of an Adequate Federal Civil Remedy?,
26 I
ND
. L.J. 361, 363 (1951).
243
Crawford-El v. Britton, 523 U.S. 574, 611 (1998) (Scalia, J., dissenting) (“Monroe
changed a statute that had generated only 21 cases in the first 50 years of its existence into
one that [generates] tens of thousands of suits each year, and engages this Court in a losing
struggle to prevent the Constitution from degenerating into a general tort law.”). One
scholar writes:
For decades, Section 1983 received a narrow interpretation by courts hostile to
expansive federal enforcement of civil rights. Not until 1961 did the Court
firmly hold that Section 1983 could remedy state violations of federal constitu-
tional rights. The combination of this decision and expansive individual rights
jurisprudence led to a mushrooming of constitutional claims . . . .
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 57 21-MAR-12 13:28
188 NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:132
sweeping remedy, but was made so by Monroe. The problem with this
inference is that until incorporation, there simply were not many fed-
eral constitutional rights that could give rise to a cause of action (to
say nothing of the pragmatic difficulties of bringing lawsuits during
Jim Crow). Equal protection claims were notoriously difficult, the
Privileges or Immunities Clause suffered narrow interpretation,
244
and
pre-incorporation Fourteenth Amendment due process did little for
civil rights plaintiffs. In the First Amendment context, the right to free
speech was incorporated in 1925,
245
free assembly in 1937,
246
free
exercise in 1940,
247
and establishment in 1947.
248
Even then, many of
these clauses did not enjoy robust interpretation until later decisions.
Although Wolf notably incorporated the right against unreasonable
searches and seizures in 1949, it explicitly relegated plaintiffs to state
common law remedies, and the Fourth Amendment’s warrant juris-
prudence was not applied to states until three years after Monroe and
Mapp.
249
This left only a handful of federal rights that could be
invoked by § 1983.
It is unsurprising, then, that the recorded cases are few and that
those that do exist are about, for example, racial discrimination in
voting rights.
250
With so few rights to assert in a § 1983 lawsuit, there
were few lawsuits. But incorporation changed that. It suddenly
increased the scope of constitutional protections to apply against state
officers. In turn, this increased the number of constitutional violations,
giving rise to more § 1983 challenges to officers’ indiscretions, which,
as we have seen, called into question whether the existing remedial
system would be up to the task. These questions all came to the sur-
face in Monroe, and the Court responded the best it could.
Finally, there is an important point to make about how incorpo-
rating the Fourth Amendment contributed to the logic of Monroe.
Prior to incorporation of the Fourth Amendment, the Constitution
had nothing to say about whether state officers could unreasonably
Sasha Samberg-Champion, How To Read Gonzaga: Laying the Seeds of a Coherent Section
1983 Jurisprudence, 103 C
OLUM
. L. R
EV
. 1838, 1842–43 (2003).
244
See, e.g., The Slaughter-House Cases, 83 U.S. 36 (1873).
245
See Gitlow v. New York, 268 U.S. 652, 666 (1925) (“[W]e may and do assume that
freedom of speech and of the press—which are protected by the First Amendment from
abridgment by Congress—are among the fundamental personal rights and ‘liberties’ pro-
tected by the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment from impairment by the
States.”).
246
De Jonge v. Oregon, 299 U.S. 353 (1937).
247
Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U.S. 296 (1940).
248
Everson v. Bd. of Educ., 330 U.S. 1 (1947).
249
See Aguilar v. Texas, 378 U.S. 108 (1964).
250
See, e.g., Nixon v. Herndon, 273 U.S. 536 (1927) (striking down a Texas statute
prohibiting Blacks from voting in Democratic party primary elections).
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 58 21-MAR-12 13:28
April 2012] THE PATH OF THE CONSTITUTION 189
search and seize; it only barred federal officers from doing so. But
after incorporation, states were denied the power to authorize unrea-
sonable searches. This meant that the enumeration principle now
applied to nullify state laws purporting to authorize anything unconsti-
tutional. As noted in the earlier cases, officers acting under unconsti-
tutional authority were acting under no authority at all, a point not
lost on either the Congress that passed § 1983 or the Court in
Monroe.
251
In every case, a plaintiff suing an officer was met by a
defense of authorization. Insofar as the officer acted within a constitu-
tionally permissible realm of discretion, there was by definition no
constitutional harm and thus no damages.
252
This created an interesting issue for § 1983. If the law motivating
the officer’s action were unconstitutional, it could not have been
authorized by the state because, quite plainly, states cannot authorize
unconstitutional laws or practices. Given that this principle was
common knowledge, it is unsurprising that the statute does not use the
word “authorize” in any form; the inquiry was not whether the state
authorized or did not authorize an unconstitutional action. Such an
inquiry confuses the analysis, mainly because the officer can never be
authorized to do something unconstitutional. Rather, the inquiry is
into whether the officer acted under color of state law.
There were two distinct ways in which a person could act “under
color of” state law. The first is best understood by analogy to agency
law. Agents of the state act under color of state law when acting
within the scope of their employment. This includes, for example, law
enforcement officers who illegally break into homes, flashing their
“star and . . . police revolver”
253
in search of evidence—even if the
state expressly forbids its officers from engaging in that kind of
behavior. According to the logic of Monroe, this is because the officer,
by representing herself as an agent of the state, and by using her office
to the unlawful end, acts under the color of state law even though she
is not and cannot be authorized to act unlawfully. By contrast, if an
off-duty officer in Las Vegas were to break into the Bellagio’s money
251
In his concurrence in Monroe, Justice Harlan wrote:
[I]f one thing is very clear in the legislative history, it is that the Congress of
1871 was well aware that no action requiring state judicial enforcement could
be taken in violation of the Fourteenth Amendment without that enforcement
being declared void by this Court on direct review from the state courts.
365 U.S. 167, 194 (1961) (Harlan, J., concurring).
252
Unless the state, through legislation, nonetheless provided for them.
253
Monroe, 365 U.S. at 238 (Frankfurter, J., dissenting).
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 59 21-MAR-12 13:28
190 NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:132
vaults in a Rat Pack–inspired heist, she would not be doing so as an
agent of the state, and thus her actions would not trigger § 1983.
254
The second way to act “under color of” state law is to run amok
as the Ku Klux Klan once did, depriving individuals of their constitu-
tional rights with reasonable knowledge, from custom, that the state
threatened no interference to their anarchy. This view of “under
color,” elucidated by a crisp understanding of how the enumeration
principle operates in the administration of remedies, explains the out-
come in Monroe.
2. Bivens v. Six Unknown Named Agents
Like Monroe, Bivens too was a response to changes in the
common law. In Bivens, the Court held that the Fourth Amendment
freedom from unreasonable searches and seizures implied a cause of
action for individuals who were deprived of that right.
255
The case,
like Mapp and Monroe, is by its own terms driven by remedies.
256
And like those cases, it can be understood only in the context of frag-
menting common law remedies.
The basic premise of the enumeration principle should need no
reiteration. A government officer with an unconstitutional defense has
no defense at all. But this is a point about government power, not
about the cause of action and the facts surrounding it. Just because the
enumeration principle invalidates an officer’s defense does not mean,
ipso facto, that the plaintiff would have a remedy against the officer as
he would against any other tortfeasor. That is, the enumeration prin-
ciple is not by itself a remedy against government misfeasance, but
rather a core doctrine that enables the system of remedies that was
imagined and assumed in 1791.
It goes without saying that a plaintiff who sues for a constitutional
harm has faced a government-imposed harm, one that is qualitatively
different from injuries imposed by private parties and one that we
associate with totalitarian states and George Orwell.
257
Just as the
Court (including the dissent) recognized in Monroe, the Court in
Bivens reiterated that despite the enumeration principle, “power,
once granted, does not disappear like a magic gift when it is wrong-
254
In fact, whether the officer was acting as an agent of the state or not could track
common law principles of respondeat superior, with § 1983 only triggered for agents.
255
Bivens v. Six Unknown Named Agents, 403 U.S. 388 (1971).
256
See generally Alfred Hill, Constitutional Remedies, 69 C
OLUM
. L. R
EV
. 1109 (1969)
(discussing the implications of these cases for judicial understanding of constitutional
remedies).
257
Perhaps a fitting place for a pun about 1983 standing before 1984.
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 60 21-MAR-12 13:28
April 2012] THE PATH OF THE CONSTITUTION 191
fully used.”
258
There is something different about an unlawful trespass
when it is committed by the government, rather than a random indi-
vidual—or at least, many would perceive such a difference.
259
The Court then described why the common law could not protect
against these harms. Every reason provided by the majority opinion
relates to the postbellum schism between common law remedies and
constitutional rights. First, the Court noted, there was a whole host of
conduct proscribed by the Fourth Amendment that was not actionable
in many states.
260
The Court had “long since rejected the notion that
the Fourth Amendment proscribes only such conduct as would, if
engaged in by private persons, be condemned by state law.”
261
Again,
the easiest example is illegal wiretapping, which, while a Fourth
Amendment violation, did not necessarily give rise to a cause of
action under state common law. The underlying concern here is that
the scope of the Fourth Amendment could not be relegated to the
whims of state tort law. Under the Court’s view, the remedy for a
clear Fourth Amendment injury should not have to depend on
whether the common law is able to keep up and provide redress for
new harms such as unauthorized wiretapping.
Second, and related, the Court recognized that as the common
law remedies took their own course, they became less and less consis-
tent with, and sometimes “even hostile” to, federal and constitutional
policy.
262
Implicit in this analysis is the consideration of several
options for navigating the Constitution’s relationship with the
common law. The analysis implicitly rejects, for example, the idea that
constitutional rights ought to depend on state common law remedies,
or the idea that the Court should monitor those remedies to make
sure that they are consistently servicing constitutional rights. Instead,
the Court in Bivens chose to provide a cause of action in a federal
forum. This cause of action would serve constitutional goals neatly
with less anxiety about collateral effects on non-constitutional litiga-
tion. Thus, the Court quite literally constitutionalized a cause of action
that could independently provide relief for constitutional injuries,
258
Bivens, 403 U.S. at 392.
259
Id. at 391–92; see also Monroe v. Pape, 365 U.S. 167, 238 (1961) (noting that the
mere appearance of official authority can be “a factor of significance in dealings between
individuals”).
260
Bivens, 403 U.S. at 392–94.
261
Id. at 392.
262
Id. at 394–95; see also id. at 409 (Harlan, J., concurring) (“It seems to me entirely
proper that these injuries be compensable according to uniform rules of federal law, espe-
cially in light of the very large element of federal law which must in any event control the
scope of official defenses to liability.”).
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 61 21-MAR-12 13:28
192 NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:132
without having to rely on the availability of adequate remedies at
common law. The next Part explores these options more explicitly.
IV
T
HE
C
ONSTITUTIONAL
O
PTIONS
There was a system of common law remedies that once worked
quite nicely as a mechanism for judicial implementation of the
Constitution.
263
So nicely, in fact, that the drafters of the Constitution
took it for granted, and even assumed a one-to-one relationship
between constitutional rights and remedies.
264
Time passed, and
entropy undermined that system of remedies, a system into which the
Bill of Rights had dug its foundations. Nonetheless, the effects of that
change would not have been felt but for major changes in American
law and society, set into motion by the usual suspects: the Civil War,
the Reconstruction amendments, urbanization and immigration, the
rise of organized police forces, the exponential growth of federal gov-
ernment, and of course, incorporation of the Bill of Rights.
These forces and others combined to create two effects relevant
to this Article: They increased the number of rights, and they
increased the number of infractions. In doing so, they hurled the Bill
of Rights into the quotidian business of American courts, trans-
forming the amendments from rights in ink into rights oft invoked.
Every day in every state, constitutional rights were violated and are
violated. Meanwhile, the common law system of remedies fragmented,
and ceased to be the neat system of enforcement it once was.
This was startling to all walks of commentators.
265
Predictably,
understandably, and to the benefit of all, commentators had different
responses, but none sat unconcerned. The order we knew had slipped
to something “simple not yet understood,” and jurists were left with
263
Of course, this system existed at the expense of officers, even those acting in good
faith. The word “nicely” here is not intended to comment on the wisdom or fairness of such
a system, but rather to suggest that there was a system of remedies ready and available to
vindicate constitutional rights.
264
As Chief Justice Marshall put it, in terms that seem too simple today, “[t]he govern-
ment of the United States has been emphatically termed a government of laws, and not of
men. It will certainly cease to deserve this high appellation, if the laws furnish no remedy
for the violation of a vested legal right.” Marbury v. Madison, 5 U.S. (1 Cranch) 137, 163
(1803).
265
Even the dissenting Justices in many of these cases expressed serious concern. See,
e.g., Bivens, 403 U.S. at 415, 421–24 (Burger, J., dissenting) (providing a list of suggestions
for congressional legislation to deal with inadequate remedies and insisting that “I do not
question the need for some remedy to give meaning and teeth to the constitutional guaran-
tees against unlawful conduct by government officials. Without some effective sanction,
these protections would constitute little more than rhetoric”).
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 62 21-MAR-12 13:28
April 2012] THE PATH OF THE CONSTITUTION 193
determining how to “make [it] good.”
266
The Court’s response came in
a series of opinions employing a similar methodology, from which this
Article selected three for consideration in light of the declining vitality
of the common law system as a vehicle for judicial implementation of
the Constitution. And when taking the arch of common law remedies
into account, these cases are remarkably explainable, and remarkably
transparent about their anxieties.
Scholars have unduly focused on Mapp, Monroe, Bivens, and
other such cases as creating an unmitigated, politically-motivated
explosion of “rights.”
267
This theory would, of course, seem true if we
ignore the dwindling availability of state law remedies that preceded
the relevant decisions. Rather than understanding these cases as a
recalibration aimed at promoting judicial efficiency and preserving the
constitutional equilibrium—motivated by concerns categorically indis-
tinct from Rehnquist Court doctrines seeking to preserve federalism
in a world that is increasingly connected by interstate commerce
268
266
E
DNA
S
T
. V
INCENT
M
ILLAY
, I will put Chaos into fourteen lines, in E
DNA
S
T
.
V
INCENT
M
ILLAY
: S
ELECTED
P
OEMS
: T
HE
C
ENTENARY
E
DITION
153, 153 (Colin Falck ed.,
Harper Collins 1991) (1954).
267
Other consequences have also followed from the failure to account for the decline of
common law remedies as a system of judicially enforcing the Constitution. As time goes
on, scholarly analysis has become thick with anachronistic assumptions. This process begins
with legal education. The Fourth, Fifth, and Sixth Amendments are taught as “criminal
procedure,” with Entick presented as a curious antecedent to modern constitutional law;
remedies are afterthoughts, things to consider once we have agreed on the contours of the
right. In this analysis, the rich historical role of common law remedies is lost in sharp
distinctions drawn between concepts of property and tort on the one hand, and criminal
procedure on the other. This is true even though, to this day, most state and federal courts
handle both criminal and civil matters. Moreover, incorporation is treated as a series of
insular decisions, not a major transition in federalism that gave rise to all sorts of (conse-
quential) procedural friction. Students learn “constitutional law” as its own coherent field,
not as a tapestry of enumerated powers that weaves in and out of the common law. As a
consequence, an understanding of the role of common law remedies in preserving life and
liberty from unconstitutional government interference is lost.
268
The intuition that the Court should recalibrate so as to keep the Constitution’s provi-
sions “meaningful” recently surfaced in Judge Sutton’s concurrence rejecting a Commerce
Clause challenge to the recent health care law. According to Judge Sutton:
At one level, past is precedent, and one tilts at hopeless causes in proposing
new categorical limits on the commerce power. But there is another way to
look at these precedents—that the Court either should stop saying that a
meaningful limit on Congress’s commerce powers exists or prove that it is so.
The stakes of identifying such a limit are high because the congressional power
to regulate is the power to preempt, a power not just to regulate a subject co-
extensively with the States but also to wipe out any contrary state laws on the
subject. U.S. C
ONST
. art. VI, cl. 2. The plaintiffs present a plausible limiting
principle, claiming that a mandate to buy medical insurance crosses a line
between regulating action and inaction, between regulating those who have
entered a market and those who have not, one that the Court and Congress
have never crossed before.
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 63 21-MAR-12 13:28
194 NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:132
critics have dismissed this era of decisions as “political.” As a result,
many have called for overturning or severely limiting these cases.
The Court has not sat agnostic. The exclusionary rule and Bivens
actions have been significantly scaled back.
269
In potential tension
with the enumeration principle, the doctrine of qualified immunity
allows courts to announce that an officer has acted unconstitutionally,
yet cloak him with immunity if “clearly established law”
270
does not
forewarn that the action was unconstitutional.
271
Even the members of
Thomas More Law Ctr. v. Obama, No. 10-2388, 2011 WL 2556039, at *22 (6th Cir. June 29,
2011) (Sutton, J., concurring). The idea implicit in this analysis is that courts can, and some-
times should, adopt tenable ways to keep the Constitution’s provisions meaningful, even if
those means are novel or, as Judge Sutton puts it, represent “line[s] . . . that the Court and
Congress have never crossed before.” Id.
269
Most recently, see Davis v. United States, 131 S. Ct. 2419, 2419 (2011), which held
that searches conducted in objectively reasonable reliance on binding appellate precedent
are not subject to the exclusionary rule. Such a holding can only be justified because the
Court currently views the exclusionary rule as a “policy” tool which is not constitutionally
required.
270
In the context of § 1983, qualified immunity is “a defense that shields officials from
suit if their conduct ‘d[id] not violate clearly established statutory or constitutional rights of
which a reasonable person would have known.’” Ortiz v. Jordan, 131 S. Ct. 884, 888 (2011)
(quoting Harlow v. Fitzgerald, 457 U.S. 800, 818 (1982)). The Supreme Court has estab-
lished a two-step test for determining whether a government official is entitled to qualified
immunity. First, a court should ask whether “the facts alleged show the officer’s conduct
violated a constitutional right.” Saucier v. Katz, 533 U.S. 194, 201 (2001), modified,
Pearson v. Callahan, 555 U.S. 223, 236 (2009). If so, then the court must determine
“whether the right was clearly established” at the time of the alleged violation. Id. The
Court has qualified this approach, stating that “the sequence set forth [in Saucier],”
although “often appropriate,” is not mandatory. Pearson, 555 U.S. at 236.
271
It is important to pause here and explain this concern. The enumeration principle, as
laid out in this paper, is an articulation of what it means to have popular sovereignty.
Power originates from the people, and the government only has power insofar as the
people granted that power to the government. In this system, a right is an exception to
conferred power—for example, the federal government has power to regulate interstate
commerce, but it may not do so in a way that violates the First Amendment. Thus, the
notion that the Court can agree that an officer violated the Constitution and yet “immu-
nize” the officer from a cause of action is in serious tension with the enumeration principle.
It allows the government to confer a protected status upon the officer, even though the
people never actually conferred this power or privilege onto the government—indeed, a
determination that the act was unconstitutional is a determination that such power was
actually withheld. Nor, if antebellum Court precedent is any indication, see supra Part I,
was this power “impliedly” conferred. Of course, there were various immunities at
common law which are not inconsistent with the enumeration principle. For example, an
officer “who arrests someone with probable cause is not liable for false arrest simply
because the innocence of the suspect is later proved.” Pierson v. Ray, 386 U.S. 547, 555
(1967) (citations omitted). That is because once an officer had probable cause, he was
legitimately vested with authority to make an arrest, and that authority could serve as a
defense in a false arrest action. Id. But modern qualified immunity has not limited itself to
this logic. See Crawford-El v. Britton, 523 U.S. 574, 611 (1998) (Scalia, J., dissenting)
(noting that the Court “has not purported to be faithful to the common-law immunities
that existed when § 1983 was enacted, and that the statute presumably intended to sub-
sume”). Indeed, in Pierson, after noting the common law example that “[a] policeman’s lot
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 64 21-MAR-12 13:28
April 2012] THE PATH OF THE CONSTITUTION 195
the Court who are most historically minded have dismissed Monroe as
engaging the Court “in a losing struggle to prevent the Constitution
from degenerating into general tort law.”
272
This is an ironic justifica-
tion for qualified immunity, as the Constitution was designed to inter-
weave into tort law, so that any officer could be sued for doing
something that violated the Constitution, but no officer could raise a
legally cognizable defense in such a suit. Thus, the Constitution does
not “degenerate” into tort law; it breathes through it. The offensive
assertion of constitutional rights, primarily through tort law, is the
remedy against officers who inflict harm on individuals without consti-
tutional authority by, for example, harassing speakers for their view-
points, or engaging in unreasonable searches and seizures without
ever pressing charges. The defensive assertion of constitutional rights
is limited for those who find themselves in lawsuits or fending off
prosecutions.
273
These assertions work in tandem, not as substitutes.
One might still think Mapp, Monroe, and Bivens were all wrong.
The purpose of this Article is not to weigh in on that discussion, but to
force the debate into more precise contours. The goal, first and fore-
most, is to understand the context in which these decisions were made.
is not so unhappy that he must choose between being charged with dereliction of duty if he
does not arrest when he has probable cause, and being mulcted in damages if he does,” the
Court went on to conclude that “the same consideration would seem to require excusing
him from liability for acting under a statute that he reasonably believed to be valid but that
was later held unconstitutional on its face or as applied.” 386 U.S. at 555. Perhaps this
reasoning can be reconciled if § 1983 only authorizes relief for “clear” constitutional trans-
gressions, and does not support a cause of action otherwise. There is no doubt that
Congress, when enacting supplementary causes of action against those acting under color
of state law, is free to require the plaintiff to show that his clearly-established right was
violated. This would then leave other violations of constitutional law (those that are
unclear) to other causes of action that are available against any individual, rather than just
officers, such as assault, false imprisonment, trespass, and other state torts, where an
officer acting without constitutional authority is—or, at least, traditionally was—treated as
having no defense at all. Assuming this correctly characterizes the text and history of the
statute, § 1983 actions seeking damages for the violation of “unclear” constitutional rights
are correctly dismissed on Rule 12(b)(6) motions for failure to state a claim—i.e., the
reason for dismissal is a failure to allege the appropriate elements of a statutory claim. A
different approach is that taken by Justice Scalia: “The § 1983 that the Court created in
1961 [in Monroe v. Pape] bears scant resemblance to what Congress enacted almost a
century earlier. . . . We find ourselves engaged, therefore, in the essentially legislative
activity of crafting a sensible scheme of qualified immunities for the statute we have
invented.” Crawford-El, 523 U.S. at 611–12 (Scalia, J., dissenting). In other words, it is
acceptable, at least in some circumstances, for a court to make up a doctrine to control the
consequences of a made-up cause of action. Of course Justice Scalia’s view is premised on
the fact that the result in Monroe was completely invented by the Court.
272
Crawford-El, 523 U.S. at 611 (Scalia, J., dissenting).
273
Of course, this Article has not strayed into discussing the writ of habeas corpus,
which can be seen as both offensive and defensive. Habeas corpus puts a prisoner or
detainee in an offensive posture against his jailor, but for the defensive reason of freeing
himself from detainment.
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 65 21-MAR-12 13:28
196 NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:132
Currently, the debate over these decisions has taken a strange form,
one not quite tethered to the problems the Court was addressing. It is
a debate over solutions without having first identified the problem.
The primary debates about judicial methodology today are, at their
most meaningless, about “judicial activism” and “judicial restraint,”
words that provide almost no uncontroversial guidance. At their most
robust, scholars, law students, and the public discuss judicial method-
ology as a debate between originalism and living constitutionalism,
and everything in between.
274
These methodologies have received their fair share of attention
and will no doubt receive more. But this debate inadequately
describes cases like Mapp, Monroe, and Bivensjudicial decisions
reached in the face of an ever-changing relationship between the
Constitution and the common law. In such cases, these “methodolo-
gies” are labels for conclusions, not instructions for judges. This
Section lays out four potential avenues of jurisprudence. None map
cleanly onto originalism or living constitutionalism; all are about the
relationship between the Constitution and the common law of the sev-
eral States. The discussion does not take a position on the wisdom or
correctness of the options; rather, it highlights some potential argu-
ments, and seeks to create a starting point for thinking about,
debating, and ultimately accepting or rejecting the various options.
A. Option 1: The Stoic Constitution
The first option is for federal courts to distinguish between
common law remedies and the Constitution, and to allow constitu-
tional rights to be expanded or contracted in accordance with the state
common law remedies that implement them. The only role that a
court would play is to uphold the enumeration principle: In any case
that comes before them, courts should interpret the Constitution
where necessary and consider unconstitutional actions null and void.
This allows judges to expound the rights that individuals do have, but
outsources the messy business of their implementation to other insti-
tutions of American democracy—state courts for interpreting state
common law, state legislatures for amending and adding to the
common law, and Congress for providing federal remedies where it
has authority and where the political process has determined that
state remedies are inadequate.
274
Compare, e.g., A
NTONIN
S
CALIA
, A M
ATTER OF
I
NTERPRETATION
: F
EDERAL
C
OURTS AND THE
L
AW
(1997) (presenting an originalist theory of constitutional interpreta-
tion), with P
AMELA
S. K
ARLAN
, G
OODWIN
L
IU
& C
HRISTOPHER
H. S
CHROEDER
, K
EEPING
F
AITH WITH THE
C
ONSTITUTION
(2009) (presenting theory of “constitutional fidelity” that
goes beyond the specific intent of the Constitution’s authors).
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 66 21-MAR-12 13:28
April 2012] THE PATH OF THE CONSTITUTION 197
The stoic constitutionalist takes this view, separates the common
law from the Constitution, and leaves the former to be implemented
and amended by public officials who are informed by (and generally
sworn to uphold) the latter. This methodology calls to mind the posi-
tion famously voiced by Learned Hand, that one should “read [the
Bill of Rights] as admonitory or hortatory, not definite enough to be
[a] guide[ ] on concrete occasions, prescribing no more than that
temper of detachment, impartiality, and an absence of self-directed
bias that is the whole content of justice . . . .”
275
Employed in Mapp,
this methodology would affirm one’s right not to be unlawfully
searched, but would defer the remedy to the state. The state could
employ the exclusionary rule, a common law cause of action for tres-
pass, or any other remedy. But if the state remedy did not provide
much—if, for example, the state had robust officer immunities, or pro-
vided only nominal damages absent physical injury, or if juries in that
state were of the law and order ilk—that would not be an issue for the
federal judiciary.
276
While it may seem that way, this is not precisely
tantamount to unincorporating the Bill of Rights. State officials, to the
extent that they are sworn to uphold the Constitution, are indeed
bound by the Bill of Rights. So, while they are free to construe the Bill
of Rights, they must at least do so in good faith.
This approach finds some accord in two major moments in feder-
alism. The first is the Madisonian Compromise, where, at the founding
debates, it was agreed that Congress would have discretion whether to
create federal courts other than the Supreme Court.
277
This contem-
plated the potential for a Union where federal courts play almost no
role in vindicating federal or constitutional rights (other than what fell
within the Supreme Court’s appellate jurisdiction, which is subject to
“Exceptions . . . [and] Regulations as the Congress shall make,” and
the Court’s original jurisdiction, which includes “all cases affecting
ambassadors, other public ministers and consuls, and those in which a
275
L
EARNED
H
AND
,T
HE
B
ILL OF
R
IGHTS
34 (1958).
276
Justice Cardozo, sitting on the high court in New York, articulated this approach in
holding that the exclusionary rule was not required by the New York Constitution. People
v. Defore, 150 N.E. 585, 589 (N.Y. 1926) (“We do not know whether the public, repre-
sented by its juries, is to-day more indifferent to its liberties than it was when the immunity
was born. If so, the change of sentiment without more does not work a change of
remedy.”).
277
See Martin H. Redish & Curtis E. Woods, Congressional Power To Control the
Jurisdiction of Lower Federal Courts: A Critical Review and a New Synthesis, 124 U. P
A
. L.
R
EV
. 45, 52–54 (1975) (describing the Compromise as “giv[ing] Congress the option to
create or not create [lower federal] courts”).
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 67 21-MAR-12 13:28
198 NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:132
state shall be party”
278
). The federal right, and the person asserting it,
would be left to the States.
The second moment is Erie Railroad Co. v. Tompkins, in which
the Court declared that “[t]here is no federal general common law,”
and that:
Congress has no power to declare substantive rules of common law
applicable in a state whether they be local in their nature or “gen-
eral,” be they commercial law or a part of the law of torts. And no
clause in the Constitution purports to confer such a power upon the
federal courts.
279
The implications of this language for the Constitution’s relationship
with the common law are unclear at best. This Article takes no posi-
tion on that question, as it is far too vast to explore here. On the one
hand, Erie could be interpreted narrowly, to hold only that when fed-
eral courts sit in diversity, they must apply state law when dealing with
substantive areas left to the states (for example, contracts and torts).
This would not disturb the application of common law remedies to
constitutional rights insofar as those remedies are deemed constitu-
tionally required. In other words, the fact that Erie says there is no
federal general common law does not foreclose federal particular
common law, including the federal common law of remedies for viola-
tion of federal rights. On the other hand, Erie provides some support
for the viewpoint taken by a stoic constitutionalist. The absence of a
federal common law might suggest that the vindication of federal
rights is not something the courts should improvise in a manner akin
to general common law, but rather a matter to be addressed by state
common law or, alternatively, statutes that Congress may pass. The
Constitution declares the rights, but allows the political process to
bring them to fruition.
This, of course, leaves much to the majorities. As Justice Holmes
put it in a letter, “I always say, as you know, that if my fellow citizens
want to go to Hell I will help them. It’s my job.”
280
The stoic constitu-
tionalist, like Justice Holmes, will have a preference for the political
process. Yes, there are constitutional rights, a stoic constitutionalist
will of course acknowledge, but courts are not the place to tease out
exact meanings from impossible ambiguities. This view is likely to
engender strong feelings. Some will no doubt feel repulsed by the pos-
sible consequences of this approach, and remember its failures, such
as when the Court deferred to democracy on the practice of
278
U.S. C
ONST
. art. III, § 2.
279
304 U.S. 64, 78 (1938).
280
Michael Herz, “Do Justice!”: Variations of a Thrice-Told Tale, 82 V
A
. L. R
EV
. 111,
114 (1996) (quoting Letter from Oliver Wendell Holmes to Harold J. Laski (Mar. 4, 1920)).
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 68 21-MAR-12 13:28
April 2012] THE PATH OF THE CONSTITUTION 199
mandatory sterilizations.
281
Others will think of its virtues, recalling
Lochner v. New York, in which Justice Holmes stated in dissent that
“[g]eneral propositions do not decide concrete cases.”
282
What scant evidence is available from the Founding suggests that
those in 1791 assumed that the common law, coupled with the enu-
meration principle, would be there to vindicate constitutional rights,
as many of them (life, liberty, and property) are and were considered
natural rights. And perhaps, then, the Due Process Clause is meant to
capture much of this, and to require that these natural rights find
some sort of vindication. The history reviewed in this Article cannot
answer this question; rather, it reveals only that the Court has, to date,
been quite anxious about stoic constitutionalism. Most notably, its
short experiment in Wolf, overturned by Mapp, suggests that it has
rejected a world in which constitutional rights are left to the devices of
common law.
In responding to concerns about dwindling common law reme-
dies, the stoic constitutionalist believes that the political process
should protect these rights, and that that process will be degraded if
participants believe the safekeeping of rights is well placed with the
federal courts. Leaving rights to federal courts might, in the long run,
be a losing proposition. The vitality of rights depends on a culture that
respects and jealously guards them; if that culture is relinquished such
that the political process is comfortable with stripping remedies for
constitutional rights, it is unclear how long judges can hold back the
tides of political sentiment, as they too are drawn from the same cul-
ture. This, of course, draws in another classic debate in law: whether
and to what extent courts actually shape culture.
283
The Court’s
response to dwindling common law remedies, as seen in Mapp,
Monroe, and Bivens, is problematic for the stoic constitutionalisthe
will maintain that the response departed from the right course and
placed the Court atop a kingdom far too vast.
B. Option 2: Rights Preservation
The second option is to do as the Court did in Mapp, Monroe,
and Bivens: adapt constitutional rights in the face of declining
281
See, e.g., Buck v. Bell, 274 U.S. 200, 207 (1927) (“Three generations of imbeciles are
enough.”).
282
198 U.S. 45, 76 (1905) (Holmes, J., dissenting).
283
See, e.g.,G
ERALD
N. R
OSENBERG
, T
HE
H
OLLOW
H
OPE
: C
AN
C
OURTS
B
RING
A
BOUT
S
OCIAL
C
HANGE
? 343 (1st ed. 1991) (discussing the debate over courts’ ability to
produce social change); Michael J. Klarman, Rethinking the Civil Rights and Civil Liberties
Revolutions, 82 V
A
. L. R
EV
. 1, 6, 19–23 (1996) (“[T]he Court’s capacity to protect minority
rights is more limited than most justices or scholars allow.”).
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 69 21-MAR-12 13:28
200 NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:132
common law remedies with the aim of maintaining some level of equi-
librium.
284
In Mapp, the Court required states to adopt the exclu-
sionary rule—a rule with origins in common law ideas about
property—as a necessary remedy for vindicating the Fourth
Amendment right to freedom from unlawful searches and seizures. As
many have pointed out, the exclusionary rule is not explicit in the
Constitution. But this does not mean that Mapp was, ipso facto, a
naked policy choice by jurists sympathetic to criminal defendants.
Rather, the Court had to select among the options set out here: (1)
essentially unincorporate the Fourth Amendment by leaving enforce-
ment to dwindling state law remedies, (2) incorporate the logic of the
common law remedy and require it as its own constitutional remedy,
namely the exclusionary rule, (3) require the common law remedies
that were available in 1868, or (4) leave enforcement to state remedies
but monitor those remedies so that they meet some federally accept-
able baseline.
The Court chose the second option for reasons made clear in its
opinion. It was committed to keeping the Fourth Amendment incor-
porated and found unpalatable the notion that the contours of that
right in practice would be shaped by circumstances of state common
law. It rejected the third and fourth options because those would
require constant oversight of state remedies, creating administrability
issues regarding how to maintain appropriate baselines. This kind of
monitoring, for which neutral principles are difficult to discern, could
significantly strain the role of federal courts in a federalist system.
So too with Monroe and Bivens. The choices were to (1) abandon
federal enforcement of constitutional rights in the face of withering
state law remedies, (2) adapt § 1983 and devise a cause of action so
that constitutional injuries would have federal remedies that are not
contingent on first spending years pursuing claims in the state systems,
(3) require state courts to provide remedies not inconsistent with
those available in 1791 and 1868, or (4) have federal courts sit as
courts of constitutional error correction for civil claims in state courts,
with federal courts deciding whether state common law practices were
interfering with the vindication of federal rights. Again, it chose the
second option, and for largely the same reasons.
In making these decisions, the Court saw itself in a familiar role,
dealing with constitutional rights the way an equity court deals with
legally protected interests, designing remedies to ensure that the right
284
See Lawrence Lessig, Fidelity in Translation, 71 T
EX
. L. R
EV
. 1165, 1166 (1993)
(“[A]ny complete account of interpretive fidelity must allow—indeed require—changes in
constitutional readings even when there has been no change in the constitutional text.”).
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 70 21-MAR-12 13:28
April 2012] THE PATH OF THE CONSTITUTION 201
would be adequately protected. By doing so, the Court has essentially
adopted a constitutional theory of remedies that has escaped much
explicit attention: that the Constitution states a purpose, as found in
its text and in the Bill of Rights, and the role of federal courts is to
implement this purpose by providing an adequate remedy for each
right. The alternative vision, adopted by the stoic constitutionalist, is
that the Constitution delegates its implementation to federalism and
the democratic process while leaving courts with only the power to
declare unconstitutional actions null and void.
C. Option 3: A Baseline System of Common Law Remedies
The third option would be to require a due process right to a
remedial process for constitutional rights that meets certain baseline
criteria. This is the equivalent of announcing that a common law
remedy for a constitutional injury is constitutionally required, and that
state courts, so long as they have general jurisdiction, must hear these
claims. Thus, actions necessary to protect constitutional rights, such as
trespass or assault, would all be constitutionally required—a state leg-
islature could not pass a law saying, for example, “no trespass actions
can result in money damages.” Moreover, the Court would enforce a
baseline set of procedures guaranteed to protect the vitality of such
suits. So, for example, a statute of limitations lasting only one week
might be constitutionally suspect insofar as it constrained the constitu-
tional right. In addition, such a view might posit that officer immuni-
ties offending the enumeration principle would be unconstitutional, as
would any regulations that burden the constitutional right as it is adju-
dicated in state courts.
The Court hinted in this direction in Wolf insofar as it relied on
the factual assumption that state courts would provide adequate reme-
dies, but it never committed itself to monitoring those remedies.
Indeed, after parties repeatedly called on the Court to monitor those
remedies, the Court backed away from Wolf entirely. The immediate
problem with this approach is apparent: What is constitutionally
required and what is not? If a week-long statute of limitations is insuf-
ficient, what would be sufficient? A month? And would all immunity
be unconstitutional? Could the state cap damages?
These are difficult and perhaps fatal questions. But one might set
the baseline as requiring a due process right to a remedial process not
inconsistent with the remedies available in 1791 and 1868—those
remedies that were available when the Bill of Rights and the
Reconstruction Era Amendments were ratified. This is analogous to
what the Court has done with the writ of habeas corpus, where it has
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 71 21-MAR-12 13:28
202 NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:132
held that “at the absolute minimum, the Suspension Clause protects
the writ ‘as it existed in 1789.’
285
But problems remain. Are all of the
features of these remedies required? Presumably the goal here is to
provide a meaningful remedy, so perhaps the Court could accept any
remedy that looks like a common law analogue, unless someone could
challenge it as insufficiently meaningful. This approach also resembles
the due process requirement that “deprivations of life, liberty, or
property by adjudication be preceded by notice and an opportunity
for a hearing appropriate to the nature of the case.”
286
Similarly, in
that context, the requirements are vague: Hearings must be “appro-
priate, fair, adequate, and such as is practicable and reasonable in the
particular case.”
287
That interpretation could be imported here,
requiring that common law remedies be similarly appropriate, fair,
adequate, and such as is practicable and reasonable.
While the Due Process Clause surely protects some baseline
amount of process, the Court did not adopt this route as a primary
way of dealing with dwindling common law remedies. The closest the
Court actually came to this approach was in Bivens, where it implied a
cause of action in federal court for constitutional injuries.
288
D. Option 4: The Laboratories of Democracy
The fourth approach, like the first, would leave the entire ques-
tion of rights and remedies to the state, accepting a diversity of
approaches. The difference is that here, the Court would monitor and
preserve a baseline of remedies in each state. This differs from option
three in that the remedies here would not have to be the ones avail-
able at common law. For example, Montana may choose to serve the
Fourth Amendment by allowing those whose rights are violated to
petition the police department to discipline the officer, and by pro-
viding state court review of this determination. At the same time, New
York may provide a trespass remedy, and Florida could employ the
exclusionary rule.
This option better describes the majority disposition in Wolf,
given that the Court’s precise reasoning was that states had adequate
remedies insofar as they had the trespass remedy or politically
accountable police departments. The Court’s legal conclusion—that
285
INS v. St. Cyr, 533 U.S. 289, 301 (2001) (quoting Felker v. Turpin, 518 U.S. 651,
663–64 (1996)).
286
16B A
M
. J
UR
. 2
D
Const. Law § 983 (2009) (citing Jones v. Flowers, 547 U.S. 220
(2006)).
287
Id. § 1007 (citations omitted).
288
403 U.S. 388, 389 (“[A] federal agent acting under color of his authority gives rise to
a cause of action for damages consequent upon his unconstitutional conduct.”).
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 72 21-MAR-12 13:28
April 2012] THE PATH OF THE CONSTITUTION 203
the absence of an exclusionary rule did not offend the Fourteenth
Amendment’s Due Process Clause—was premised on the factual con-
clusion that states had remedies other than the exclusionary rule that
were sufficient to satisfy due process.
289
The implication here is that
the Court could review each system of remedies to ensure that they
were sufficient to protect the constitutional right at stake. Thus, if a
state provided no remedy whatsoever, the Court could default to
requiring exclusion or some other remedy so as to satisfy whatever the
Due Process Clause may require.
This state-by-state approach also mirrors the Court’s general
monitoring of constitutional issues in state criminal trials on a case-by-
case basis. For example, in Penry v. Lynaugh,
290
the Court developed
a doctrine designed specifically in the context of Texas’s death penalty
regime. The Constitution allows Texas to impose the death penalty
(even on mentally retarded offenders, at least until the Court’s deci-
sion in Atkins v. Virginia
291
), and to regulate its criminal justice
system in general, but cases like Penry step in when aspects of that
system fall beneath a constitutional threshold—there, the adequacy of
the jury instructions as they pertained to mitigating evidence.
292
This,
of course, is not unfamiliar. It is, in essence, how federalism works
between state and federal courts—the state courts handle matters
within their jurisdiction, and the Supreme Court can correct federal or
constitutional errors as they arise. There is some reason to think this is
how the Court will approach restrictions on Second Amendment
rights. Rather than requiring any particular regime, the Court will
accept as-applied challenges to particular features of different state
regulations.
293
Similarly, in determining the adequacy of state law
remedies for constitutional rights, the Court could develop case-by-
case doctrines depending on what avenue of relief a state chooses to
provide.
Again, the history seems agnostic on this, offering little more
than the Court’s rejection of this methodology after briefly flirting
289
Wolf v. Colorado, 338 U.S. 25, 31 (1949) (“[T]he exclusion of evidence may be an
effective way of deterring unreasonable searches, [but] it is not for this Court to condemn
as falling below the minimal standards assured by the Due Process Clause a State’s reliance
upon other methods which, if consistently enforced, would be equally effective.”).
290
492 U.S. 302 (1989).
291
536 U.S. 304 (2002) (holding that death is an “excessive” punishment for a mentally
retarded criminal, in violation of the Eighth Amendment).
292
Penry, 492 U.S. at 328 (holding in part that Texas could not execute the defendant
because the jury had not been adequately instructed to consider mitigating evidence).
293
See, e.g., McDonald v. City of Chicago, 130 S. Ct. 3020 (2010) (holding that the
Second Amendment, by virtue of the Fourteenth, should be applied in a challenge against
two Illinois cities’ handgun bans and several related city ordinances).
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 73 21-MAR-12 13:28
204 NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:132
with it in Wolf. One major concern, of course, is that this approach
would submerge the courts with litigation challenging various aspects
of state remedies, particularly tort remedies, until all of the non-
frivolous and many of the frivolous challenges had been exhausted. It
also invites the Court to rummage around state procedures, inspecting
them for overall federal quality. This is something of an uncomfort-
able position for a federal court, and certainly less administrable than,
for example, simply requiring the exclusionary rule.
C
ONCLUSION
Perhaps, of the four options available to the Court, we could con-
clusively decide that one makes the most sense from, for example, an
originalist perspective. But that is precisely the question: Which of
these options makes the most sense and why? This was the question
the Court was tackling in the discussed cases and the question this
Article seeks to bring back to prominence. The narrative here began
with answering questions—what happened to the original system of
remedies and how did the Court respond?—but now ends by posing
an even more difficult question: What is the appropriate way to deal
with constitutional rights that are being deflated by dwindling
common law remedies?
The answer to this question should be the focus of debate. The
history highlighted in this Article reveals that these cases have been
criticized without a firm understanding of what exactly they were
resolving: how to negotiate the changing relationship between the
Constitution and the common law remedies that were assumed to
implement the Constitution. How we resolve each case in turn defines
the relationship between the Constitution and the common law.
294
Thus, the most important lesson the history may provide is not
how to answer each specific question, but that we should answer the
specific questions with an overarching and principled understanding
294
A good example is United States v. Jones, No. 10-1259 (U.S. Jan. 23, 2012)—handed
down too late for this Article to discuss substantively—in which the Court held that the use
of a GPS device to monitor a vehicle’s movements for an extended period of time consti-
tutes a search for purposes of the Fourth Amendment. There, Justice Scalia wrote for the
majority—which included Chief Justice Roberts, Justice Kennedy, Justice Thomas, and
Justice Sotomayor—that the Fourth Amendment protects, “at a minimum,” slip op. at
10–11, the degree of protection afforded by the 18th-century trespass remedy against
searches of “persons, houses, papers, and effects.” Id. at n.8. By contrast, Justice Alito’s
concurrence, joined by Justices Ginsburg, Breyer, and Kagan, derided the reliance on
“18th-century tort law,” concurring op. at 1, suggesting that “it is almost impossible to
think of late 18th-century situations that are analogous” to GPS devices. Concurring op. at
3. As the lineup in Jones suggests, where one lands on this issue depends not on politics or
ideology, but on how one understands the relationship between constitutional rights and
the common law remedies that once protected them.
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 74 21-MAR-12 13:28
April 2012] THE PATH OF THE CONSTITUTION 205
of how the Constitution relates to the common law. It makes little
sense simply to endorse or reject the exclusionary rule. That position
should be the outcome produced by a defensible theory of constitu-
tional remedies. The relevant question is whether the Mapp-Monroe-
Bivens approach is correct because the Court is supposed to maintain
remedies so as to preserve constitutional rights, or is wrong because,
as the stoic constitutionalist would suggest, the common law remedies
are severable from the Constitution, and a remedy does not necessa-
rily inhere to constitutional rights.
In other words, we should stop debating these decisions as though
they are merely the outcome of policy debates among judges. The
problem with doing so is two fold. First, it is descriptively wrong and
unfair to the jurists who wrestled with the more complex issues.
Second, it implies that such precedent is somehow less legitimate
because it is “policy,” and thus can be replaced with other “policy”
decisions.
295
This unnecessarily politicizes the judiciary by implying
that jurists merely determine legal policy. They do not, or at least,
they should not be doing so. The task, rather, is to determine what to
do when constitutional rights were crafted on the assumption that
there would always be common law remedies to address them,
particularly now that common law remedies have atrophied in impor-
tant ways.
Thus perhaps the primary constitutional debate should not be
between “living constitutionalists” and “originalists,” given that all of
the possible options require taking some action (or inaction) that was
not contemplated in 1791 or 1868. Rather, the debate should be which
set of actions is most consistent with the principle and structure of the
Constitution as it was ratified in 1791 and 1868—and that, unfortu-
nately, is not an easy question.
This Article explores the idea of “constitutional rights” by telling
the story of their judicial enforcement, particularly how the nature of
that enforcement was threatened, and how the Court responded. It
does not attack or defend the Court’s response, but understands it in
the context of these challenges. That exercise ended by teasing out
four jurisprudential options. None of these options are entirely satis-
fying. Deflating the constitutional rights embodied in cases like Mapp,
Monroe, and Bivens without restoring the original system of constitu-
tional remedies would result in a net loss for constitutional rights—a
295
For example, because the Court has come to understand the exclusionary rule as a
prudential doctrine and a policy tool, it now determines whether exclusion should apply on
the basis of whether its application would constitute sound policy. See, e.g., Davis v. United
States, 131 S. Ct. 2419, 2427 (2011) (applying the rule that courts should weigh the “real
deterrent value” against the “substantial social costs” of exclusion).
\\jciprod01\productn\N\NYU\87-1\NYU104.txt unknown Seq: 75 21-MAR-12 13:28
206 NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:132
result inconsistent, or at least in deep tension with, originalist princi-
ples. After all, the Framers preserved these rights not because they
are interesting in the abstract, but because they are fundamental to a
free life. Yet preserving these liberties by adhering to Mapp, Monroe,
and Bivens poses its own challenges for originalism. At the same time,
discarding these cases and opting to keep alive the original system of
remedies could deeply threaten values inherent in federalism—again,
in a way not originally contemplated. At end, there is no easy answer
for which methodology most faithfully serves our Constitution, but for
those who care about the reality of constitutional rights, this is the
question.